My advisor just solved Kakeya in three dimensions, here is why that matters
by greenturtle3141, Mar 14, 2025, 8:14 PM
Reading Difficulty: anywhere between 2 and 5 out of 5
On March 10th, 3:30 pm, Room 1302 of the Courant Institute of Mathematics was at its liveliest in years. With every seat filled, the unfortunate late-comers were doomed to sitting on tables or simply standing along the edges of the lecture room. There was barely any room to breathe, but the air was no less vibrant with excitement and anticipation, with students and professors alike straining their necks in search of the seemingly absent speaker. The speaker's absence was no mystery, however --- the talk was not to start for another 15 long minutes.
As the room continued to fill up, it became increasingly clear to me that this would be no ordinary mathematical colloquium. After all, in a stunning 127-page paper, Hong Wang had recently proven the Kakeya Conjecture in
, a notorious problem in the field of geometric measure theory. The proof took the mathematical world by storm, with reknowned mathematicians in the field hailing the paper as a major breakthrough. With such an achievement that few could ever hope to claim, it is no surprise that a horde of faculty and PhD students from a wide spectrum of mathematical subfields, from fluid dynamics to algebraic geometry to stochastic calculus, were here to witness history in the making. By 3:40 pm, the lecture room's occupancy was undoubtedly violating several federal fire codes, and at last, not too long after, Hong's eagerly-awaited appearance was greeted with a thunderous applause from an audience of no less than 100.
I couldn't find the fire codes for the building online, but I'm quite confident that this room was not meant to house more than 50 people.
What is the Kakeya Conjecture?
Take a needle of length 1. If I want to spin it, one way to do that is to spin it around its center
. The area it sweeps out would thus be a circle of diameter
.
If you're feeling feisty, you might want to try to spin it in such a way that the area swept out by the needle is as small as possible. How small can this area get? Besicovitch proved that the area can be arbitrarily small. Below is an example (graphics stolen from Wikipedia) whose area is supposedly
.
The above examples are nice for explaining this problem to laymen, but the Kakeya conjecture is about a more general class of shapes called Kakeya sets --- sets that contain a unit line segment in every direction. (Sometimes these are also called Besicovitch sets.) Such objects are of interest not just in the plane, but in arbitrary dimensions as well. Besicovitch's discovery shows that the size of Kakeya sets can be as close to
as you want, and in fact, could even have a size of exactly
. The Kakeya conjecture asks if Kakeya sets can be even smaller than that.
To make this more precise, let's take the two dimensional case as an example.
So, dimension can be used to in some sense quantify the size of sets that have zero measure. The larger the dimension, the "larger" such a set is. The Kakeya conjecture states that Kakeya sets are actually not that small at all.
Kakeya Conjecture in
: Every Kakeya set in the plane is at least two-dimensional. (...thus exactly two-dimensional.)
This conjecture generalizes.
Kakeya Conjecture in
: Every Kakeya set in
-dimensional space is
-dimensional.
(Actually the conjecture in
isn't a conjecture --- it's been fully solved for a while now.)
What is "dimension"?
The word dimension is actually quite vague to a mathematician. You really have to specify what type of dimension you're talking about. Even as it pertains to measure theory and/or geometry, there are still several different notions of "dimension". The main types of interest here are the Hausdorff dimension and the Minkowski dimension. The Hausdorff dimension is a bit more proper but it's harder to explain. The Minkowski dimension is easier to explain.
Let's stay in 3D space to motivate this. How can we study the "size" of a 2-dimensional object (living in 3D space), like a filled-in unit square, using only the notion of volume (i.e. "3D size")? Taking the volume of the square gives you zero, so that's not good. What you can do instead is fatten up the object so that it has volume. If you take a neighborhood of the square, you get (ignoring the curvy parts) a rectangular prism of dimensions
, where
is how much we fatten up the square, so the volume of the fattened square is about
.
We can do the same idea for studying a (unit) line segment: If we fatten this up, we get (ignoring the parts at the ends) a cylinder with a base of radius
, so its volume is about
.
Finally, we can try this out for studying just a single point. Fattening this up gives us a sphere with volume
.
Notice that the less dimensions the object has, the bigger the exponent of
, with an exponent of
representing the smallest possible dimension. This lets us define a notion of dimension.
Definition (Minkowski Dimension in
): Let
be a set in
. The Minkowski dimenson of
is the number
(if it exists) for which

This generaizes nicely to arbitrary dimensions.
Definition (Minkowski Dimension in
): Let
be a set in
. The Minkowski dimenson of
is the number
(if it exists) for which

So a (slightly weaker) form of the Kakeya conjecture is that every Kakeya set in
has Minkowski dimension
. It turns out that if you prove this for Hausdorff dimension instead, you automatically get it for Minkowski dimension as well.
Hong Wang (joint with Joshua Zahl) managed to prove this statement (for both notions of dimension) for
. It's pretty complicated.
What should I care about this result?
There is a certain heirarchy of seemingly unrelated conjectures that are in play here. The first is the Local Smoothing Conjecture for the wave equation, first formulated by Sogge.
Conjecture: Let
solve the wave equation in
dimensions with initial data
and
. Let*
be a compact subinterval of time. Then** for every
and
, we have

(* In the literature they always take this to be
. I don't know why but I don't think the choice is important.)
(** There is also stuff conjectured for
but I don't really care.)
Essentially this conjecture is asking whether integrability and regularity is lost as waves travel. The conjecture says that you don't lose too much, with the caveat that you first average your solution over a small time interval (hence the word "local"). Hilariously, the first proof of this conjecture for some value of
was given by Wolff: For dimension
and
(that number is not a typo!!!).
The next conjecture is the restriction conjecture.
Conjecture: The inequality
holds for all test functions
if and only if
and
, where
is the Holder conjugate of
.
Intuitively, this question asks if anything terrible happens if I look at the Fourier transform of a function over a surface. The conjecture states that it's not too terrible.
This sequence of conjectures can be made longer but I'll just say that Kakeya is the last one in the chain.
Conjecture: Every Kakeya set in
has Hausdorff and Minkowski dimension
.
For bizarre reasons, we have the following chain of implications:
It is not known if any of these implications can be reversed, though there are some partial results on this matter. Nevertheless, what this means is that if we can't solve Kakeya then we sure as heck can't solve the restriction conjecture or the local smoothing conjecture. Technically speaking, we would get more if Kakeya were somehow proven to be false. Since Kakeya was successfully proven in 3 dimensions, the other two conjectures are still wide open in 3 dimensions.
Many other wildly different parts of mathematics have been used to attack Kakeya, such as additive combinatorics. In the other direction, the theory surrounding Kakeya sets has also been used as the catalyst for proving things. The main such result (that I know of) is actually a negative result related to Fourier analysis. We know that for
sufficiently nice we have
and so it is very natural to ask whether
converges to
in a nice way as
.
In dimension
it's very nice: We have that
in
for all
. (Here
is assumed to be a Schwarz function so that its Fourier transform makes sense.) It's also true for
in arbitrary dimensions, which is "trivial": We may write
as
(hence why this is called a "disk multiplier problem"), then since Fourier transform is an
isometry we have
which obviously (to those for which this is obvious) goes to
as
.
So, what about for higher dimensions
and exponents
? Mathematicians were stuck on proving this until Fefferman ruined everyone's day by showing that it's completely false. He did this by using a Kakeya set to build a function
for which
is small but
is huge. Roughly speaking, this is done by designing
to be a bunch of thin rectangles that are spread out, such that the disk multiplier shifts all these rectangles to overlap like a Kakeya set, causing an explosion.
In sum, Kakeya theory has a ton of fascinating connections to other fields. For now, most of these connections are of the form "this field can be applied to help prove Kakeya". Nevertheless, the methodologies developed for attacking Kakeya are themselves very important results with a variety of implications, and I do find myself quite curious about trying to reverse things and using Kakeya to attack other fields. It's quite possible that I'm being very naive and that such reversals are unrealistic to achieve. But I very much would like to try and find such results, since it would make this theory all the more rich.
Can you give a summary of how the proof works?
Reading Difficulty: 11 out of 5
I obviously did not actually read the paper because it's very long and I'm also not quite learned enough in this field to effectively digest it, aside from snippets of the introductory sections. Fortunately it turns out that I managed to snag a front-row seat for Hong's talk, so here's an overview of what's going on from what I can gather.
First, here's a history lesson. For a Kakeya set in
, one can slightly fatten a selection of the line segments in this Kakeya set and study how much bigger it gets. Using this idea, one can find that the statement "every Kakeya set in
has dimension
" reduces to proving an inequality of the following form: For every
there is a constant
such that for all sufficiently small
,
for every
where
is (an arbitrary) collection of
-separated (in angle) tubes of length 1 and radius
. Also
(the Holder conjugate).
There are a truckload of quantifiers here so we like to shorten this proposition as:
Note that the number of tubes is about
so this is trivial for
(after raising each side to
so that the LHS is actually a norm). What we want to do is get
to be as small as possible, and we win if we can get down to
.
Cordoba proved this inequaity for
(corresponding to
) using a dumb argument, which is now a classic trick. First you write
Then you split up the sum according to the scale of the angle between the tubes. Formally speaking we partition the range of possible angles
dyadically as
,
, and so on. There are like
possible scales, and morally
, so we can toss out that factor and just look at tubes that intersect at an angle of approximately
. By a counting argument there are
pairs of tubes that intersect at an angle of (up to a factor of 2)
. If you draw what that looks like, you find that the volume of the intersection is at most
. So the sum of these intersections over all such pairs is like
. Clearly only the
term is dominant so we get the upper bound
, and the exponent we wanted was
, so we're chilling.
That last sentence suggests that this was a pretty wasteful argument, and Bourgain agreed. He one-upped Cordoba by getting
down to
, which corresponds to
. I don't actually know what this argument is.
(A guy named Drury also one-upped Cordoba, but only in higher dimensions.)
Then Wolff woke up and chose violence. He skill-issued everyone by getting
down to
, which corresponds to
. He did this using some black magic semi-inspired by what Drury did. Basically, Drury took advantage of the fact that lines can only intersect once, and Wolff took this further by using the fact that three lines make a triangle. (If you're getting the sense that I'm oversimplifying, you are 100% correct.) Wolff's proof is now known as the hairbrush argument, and I won't describe it because it is very long.
Then people got stuck for a while. There's a really interesting reason for that: None of the above proofs really use the fact that the underlying field of
is
. For example the Cordoba argument works perfectly fine if our setting was
. (The finite field case is also of interest, and if you think about it for a minute you'll find that the Cordoba argument in this setting is super stupid because there are literally only two possible angles.) The reason why this philosophically represents a problem is that if we work in
, then Wolff's bound of
is the (kinda) best possible!
A counterexample is given by what is called the Heisenberg group on
(which, as far as I can tell is not exactly the same as the "Heienberg group" you find on Wikipedia), given by the set
It turns out that
is a
-dimensional set, which is morally
(complex) dimesions. It's also kinda a Kakeya set, so this is a kinda-counterexample. (To be more precise, it is a counterexample to a stronger version of the Kakeya conjecture which has the more relaxed assumpion called the Wolff axioms).
So, philosophically, if you want to beat Wolff's hairbrush proof, you have to do something tricky that takes advantage of the exact structure of the real numbers. For example, the reals does not have a "half-dimensional" subfield like the complex numbers do. To wit, via a 64-page paper, Katz, Łaba and Tao managed to prove the bound
in the year 2000.
(That extra
isn't an exaggeration by the way!)
Their paper essentially proves that if a Kakeya set's dimension is big enough then it needs to exhibit three properties, which they call stickiness, planiness, and graininess. (The word "sticky" means "stick-like", not "glue-like") So sets of these sorts became of interest to study.
Mathematicians were stuck for another 25 years because this problem is very hard. Now let me try to talk about what Hong Wang did. I am not an expert on this (yet) so you probably shouldn't cite this post for anything.
So, the Kakeya conjecture roughly reduces to proving an inequality that looks kinda like
where
is a collection of about
tubes of size
, contained in like a
box, and satisfying the condition
: "All tubes are
-separated in angle". This turns out to be hard, so I believe they prove a different statement that's more complicated but still enough to resolve Kakeya. Don't ask me what it is. I said don't. Stop. Shush.
Anyways, they want to use something called an induction on scales argument. Essentially this boils down to something like this:
Now, there are two problems here that kinda clash with each other in trying to execute this protocol. On one hand, the assumption
is not preserved when we go through the "inductive step". So you might be tempted to throw it out. On the other hand, the conjecture is false without the assumption
: Take a
slab and draw every possible
tube inside it. There are about
such tubes. However the volume of their union is approximately
, which is certainly not
.
The idea to fix this is, instead of tossing
, we replace it with a pair of axioms that do get preserved under scaling shenanigans:
At this point in the talk Hong gave us the exercise to find trivial upper (resp. lower) bounds on
assuming the KTW (resp. FW) axioms. And she made us think about it which was incredibly funny. So I'll now give you the opportunity to think about them as well. (I managed to answer the second one so it's not hard I swear!)
.
.
.
Alright let's talk about it.
We are allowed to replace the assumption
with these axioms because these axioms are both implied by
. Proof
Supposedly, if
satisfies the KTW axioms, then one can show that
, which I believe means you essentially win.
Now let's talk a bit more on how the induction on scales work, as I understand it. Define
to be the number of
-tubes in
that pass through a typical point in
. The goal essentially reduces to studying this
quantity. Now, for each
, which represents a larger "scale", gather up most of these
-tubes into large
tubes.
![[asy]
size(3inches);
real r1 = 0.05;
real r2 = 0.3;
path t1 = (1,r1)--(-1,r1)--(-1,-r1)--(1,-r1)--cycle;
path t2 = (1,r2)--(-1,r2)--(-1,-r2)--(1,-r2)--cycle;
pair[] xs = intersectionpoints(rotate(35, (0,0)) * t1, rotate(-10, (0,0)) * t2);
fill(rotate(30, (0,0)) * t2, p=gray(0.9));
fill(rotate(-10, (0,0)) * t2, p=gray(0.9));
fill(rotate(35, (0,0)) * t1, p=gray(0.6));
fill(rotate(22, (0,0)) * t1, p=gray(0.6));
fill(rotate(-3, (0,0)) * t1, p=gray(0.6));
fill(rotate(-15, (0,0)) * t1, p=gray(0.6));
fill(rotate(-20, (0,0)) * t1, p=gray(0.6));
fill(xs[0]--xs[1]--xs[2]--xs[3]--cycle, p=red);
draw(rotate(30, (0,0)) * t2, p=linewidth(1.3));
draw(rotate(-10, (0,0)) * t2, p=linewidth(1.3));
draw(rotate(35, (0,0)) * t1);
draw(rotate(22, (0,0)) * t1);
draw(rotate(-3, (0,0)) * t1);
draw(rotate(-15, (0,0)) * t1);
draw(rotate(-20, (0,0)) * t1);
[/asy]](//latex.artofproblemsolving.com/texer/r/rvltzlrl.png)
The larger
-tubes form a new collection of tubes
, which we can also study with this
function, defined in the same way for these new tubes. Now, in the "sticky case",
is not too big for every
, and I think in this case we're happy for some reason. In the "non-sticky case", there is some
for which
. I think this is the case that is assumed going forward.
Previously it was observed that
for a typical
-tube
. For some reason this isn't good enough, for the induction on scales, so it appears that they managed to prove
where
is a collection of tubes of size about
that you get after taking the
-tubes and chopping off the parts that aren't in
. An example is shaded in red in the above diagram.
If you feel that
is weird, your gut instinct is correct ---
hasn't been studied very much by researchers because it has no a priori structure. Fortunately, today it can now be analyzed thanks to a certain factoring proposition. Essentially, it states that if you're given a bunch of tubes, you can throw out just a few of them so that the rest can be grouped in a nice way. More precisely (in the sense that this is what was written on the board during the talk), if
is a collection of
-tubes, then there is a subcollection
with
and a set
of
boxes (where
are determined by
) such that
That's it for my overview. Happy
day.
On March 10th, 3:30 pm, Room 1302 of the Courant Institute of Mathematics was at its liveliest in years. With every seat filled, the unfortunate late-comers were doomed to sitting on tables or simply standing along the edges of the lecture room. There was barely any room to breathe, but the air was no less vibrant with excitement and anticipation, with students and professors alike straining their necks in search of the seemingly absent speaker. The speaker's absence was no mystery, however --- the talk was not to start for another 15 long minutes.
As the room continued to fill up, it became increasingly clear to me that this would be no ordinary mathematical colloquium. After all, in a stunning 127-page paper, Hong Wang had recently proven the Kakeya Conjecture in


I couldn't find the fire codes for the building online, but I'm quite confident that this room was not meant to house more than 50 people.
What is the Kakeya Conjecture?
Take a needle of length 1. If I want to spin it, one way to do that is to spin it around its center


![[asy]
size(3cm);
fill(circle((0,0),1/2), p=gray(0.9));
draw(circle((0,0),1/2), p=linewidth(1.5));
[/asy]](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/e/2/e/e2e4b618306e02ef763c74ed4035e3f9f8d674db.png)
If you're feeling feisty, you might want to try to spin it in such a way that the area swept out by the needle is as small as possible. How small can this area get? Besicovitch proved that the area can be arbitrarily small. Below is an example (graphics stolen from Wikipedia) whose area is supposedly


The above examples are nice for explaining this problem to laymen, but the Kakeya conjecture is about a more general class of shapes called Kakeya sets --- sets that contain a unit line segment in every direction. (Sometimes these are also called Besicovitch sets.) Such objects are of interest not just in the plane, but in arbitrary dimensions as well. Besicovitch's discovery shows that the size of Kakeya sets can be as close to


To make this more precise, let's take the two dimensional case as an example.
- An example of a shape with
area could be something like a circle with a ton of tiny holes punched into it. It has no area, but it's still a 2-dimensional object.
- Another example is a line. Lines have zero area. But they're definitely "smaller" than 2-dimensional objects. In fact, lines have only 1 dimension.
- Another example is a dot, a single point. A single point has no area, the same area as a line, but intuitively a single dot is far smaller than a line. Using the concept of dimension makes this intuition clearer: A single point has zero dimensions.
So, dimension can be used to in some sense quantify the size of sets that have zero measure. The larger the dimension, the "larger" such a set is. The Kakeya conjecture states that Kakeya sets are actually not that small at all.
Kakeya Conjecture in

This conjecture generalizes.
Kakeya Conjecture in



(Actually the conjecture in

What is "dimension"?
The word dimension is actually quite vague to a mathematician. You really have to specify what type of dimension you're talking about. Even as it pertains to measure theory and/or geometry, there are still several different notions of "dimension". The main types of interest here are the Hausdorff dimension and the Minkowski dimension. The Hausdorff dimension is a bit more proper but it's harder to explain. The Minkowski dimension is easier to explain.
Let's stay in 3D space to motivate this. How can we study the "size" of a 2-dimensional object (living in 3D space), like a filled-in unit square, using only the notion of volume (i.e. "3D size")? Taking the volume of the square gives you zero, so that's not good. What you can do instead is fatten up the object so that it has volume. If you take a neighborhood of the square, you get (ignoring the curvy parts) a rectangular prism of dimensions



We can do the same idea for studying a (unit) line segment: If we fatten this up, we get (ignoring the parts at the ends) a cylinder with a base of radius


Finally, we can try this out for studying just a single point. Fattening this up gives us a sphere with volume

Notice that the less dimensions the object has, the bigger the exponent of


Definition (Minkowski Dimension in






This generaizes nicely to arbitrary dimensions.
Definition (Minkowski Dimension in






So a (slightly weaker) form of the Kakeya conjecture is that every Kakeya set in


Hong Wang (joint with Joshua Zahl) managed to prove this statement (for both notions of dimension) for

What should I care about this result?
There is a certain heirarchy of seemingly unrelated conjectures that are in play here. The first is the Local Smoothing Conjecture for the wave equation, first formulated by Sogge.
Conjecture: Let








(* In the literature they always take this to be
![$I = [1,2]$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/d/9/6/d96a8bd65e6f39376a23515672afd41c88c8e035.png)
(** There is also stuff conjectured for

Essentially this conjecture is asking whether integrability and regularity is lost as waves travel. The conjecture says that you don't lose too much, with the caveat that you first average your solution over a small time interval (hence the word "local"). Hilariously, the first proof of this conjecture for some value of



The next conjecture is the restriction conjecture.
Conjecture: The inequality






Intuitively, this question asks if anything terrible happens if I look at the Fourier transform of a function over a surface. The conjecture states that it's not too terrible.
This sequence of conjectures can be made longer but I'll just say that Kakeya is the last one in the chain.
Conjecture: Every Kakeya set in


For bizarre reasons, we have the following chain of implications:

Many other wildly different parts of mathematics have been used to attack Kakeya, such as additive combinatorics. In the other direction, the theory surrounding Kakeya sets has also been used as the catalyst for proving things. The main such result (that I know of) is actually a negative result related to Fourier analysis. We know that for





In dimension












So, what about for higher dimensions






In sum, Kakeya theory has a ton of fascinating connections to other fields. For now, most of these connections are of the form "this field can be applied to help prove Kakeya". Nevertheless, the methodologies developed for attacking Kakeya are themselves very important results with a variety of implications, and I do find myself quite curious about trying to reverse things and using Kakeya to attack other fields. It's quite possible that I'm being very naive and that such reversals are unrealistic to achieve. But I very much would like to try and find such results, since it would make this theory all the more rich.
Can you give a summary of how the proof works?
Reading Difficulty: 11 out of 5
I obviously did not actually read the paper because it's very long and I'm also not quite learned enough in this field to effectively digest it, aside from snippets of the introductory sections. Fortunately it turns out that I managed to snag a front-row seat for Hong's talk, so here's an overview of what's going on from what I can gather.
First, here's a history lesson. For a Kakeya set in












There are a truckload of quantifiers here so we like to shorten this proposition as:






Cordoba proved this inequaity for



![$[\delta,1]$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/5/4/c/54c48d536e16181c05271e6f180a7b95af513a52.png)
![$[1/2,1]$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/5/5/8/5581510e950d8ceb9bcbcfd0dc988d9c4538c684.png)
![$[1/4,1/2]$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/c/e/7/ce7b57517ee6f8c28c1f5215b9bac80bd95dc730.png)










That last sentence suggests that this was a pretty wasteful argument, and Bourgain agreed. He one-upped Cordoba by getting



(A guy named Drury also one-upped Cordoba, but only in higher dimensions.)
Then Wolff woke up and chose violence. He skill-issued everyone by getting



Then people got stuck for a while. There's a really interesting reason for that: None of the above proofs really use the fact that the underlying field of





A counterexample is given by what is called the Heisenberg group on





So, philosophically, if you want to beat Wolff's hairbrush proof, you have to do something tricky that takes advantage of the exact structure of the real numbers. For example, the reals does not have a "half-dimensional" subfield like the complex numbers do. To wit, via a 64-page paper, Katz, Łaba and Tao managed to prove the bound

(That extra

Their paper essentially proves that if a Kakeya set's dimension is big enough then it needs to exhibit three properties, which they call stickiness, planiness, and graininess. (The word "sticky" means "stick-like", not "glue-like") So sets of these sorts became of interest to study.
Mathematicians were stuck for another 25 years because this problem is very hard. Now let me try to talk about what Hong Wang did. I am not an expert on this (yet) so you probably shouldn't cite this post for anything.
So, the Kakeya conjecture roughly reduces to proving an inequality that looks kinda like







Anyways, they want to use something called an induction on scales argument. Essentially this boils down to something like this:
- You have a bunch of
tubes.
- You want to group them together into big bundles of tubes. (I am very clearly oversimplifying.)
- These big bundles now look something like, I dunno,
tubes. (I didn't actually read the technicalities of this induction. Don't quote me.)
- So in some sense you can reduce to solving the problem for tubes of slightly larger radius.
- Now you induct upwards, getting larger and larger radii, until you hit a base case and you win.
Now, there are two problems here that kinda clash with each other in trying to execute this protocol. On one hand, the assumption







The idea to fix this is, instead of tossing

- The Katz-Tao-Wolff axioms (KTW), in which
satisfies the following condition: For every rectangular prism
, the cardinality of the set
satisfies the bound
- The Frostman-Wolff axioms (FW), in which
satisfies the following condition: For every rectangular prism
, we have
the bound
At this point in the talk Hong gave us the exercise to find trivial upper (resp. lower) bounds on

.
.
.
Alright let's talk about it.
- If
satisfies the KTW axioms, then by taking
to be the entire
box, we have that
and
is approximately
. So
. Hence a trival upper bound is
divided by the volume of a typical tube (i.e. like
). The intuition here is that in this case
is small enough that it is "sparse", and so we expect the tubes to be "essentially disjoint".
- If
satisfies the FW axioms, then by taking
to just be one of our tubes (in this field rectangular prisms and tubes are viewed as basically the same thing so this is kosher), we have
and so
. So this time we get
. The intuition here is that in this case
is big enough that it should "fill out the whole
cube".
We are allowed to replace the assumption


I started to write a proof and then realized I didn't actually know how to prove this. Maybe I'll fill this in when I figure it out but realistically I'm probably going to be too lazy to edit this post. So here's a joke instead.
...I was going to write a joke but then I realized I didn't have one. Well this is awkward. I need to finish writing this post.
...I was going to write a joke but then I realized I didn't have one. Well this is awkward. I need to finish writing this post.
Supposedly, if


Now let's talk a bit more on how the induction on scales work, as I understand it. Define








![[asy]
size(3inches);
real r1 = 0.05;
real r2 = 0.3;
path t1 = (1,r1)--(-1,r1)--(-1,-r1)--(1,-r1)--cycle;
path t2 = (1,r2)--(-1,r2)--(-1,-r2)--(1,-r2)--cycle;
pair[] xs = intersectionpoints(rotate(35, (0,0)) * t1, rotate(-10, (0,0)) * t2);
fill(rotate(30, (0,0)) * t2, p=gray(0.9));
fill(rotate(-10, (0,0)) * t2, p=gray(0.9));
fill(rotate(35, (0,0)) * t1, p=gray(0.6));
fill(rotate(22, (0,0)) * t1, p=gray(0.6));
fill(rotate(-3, (0,0)) * t1, p=gray(0.6));
fill(rotate(-15, (0,0)) * t1, p=gray(0.6));
fill(rotate(-20, (0,0)) * t1, p=gray(0.6));
fill(xs[0]--xs[1]--xs[2]--xs[3]--cycle, p=red);
draw(rotate(30, (0,0)) * t2, p=linewidth(1.3));
draw(rotate(-10, (0,0)) * t2, p=linewidth(1.3));
draw(rotate(35, (0,0)) * t1);
draw(rotate(22, (0,0)) * t1);
draw(rotate(-3, (0,0)) * t1);
draw(rotate(-15, (0,0)) * t1);
draw(rotate(-20, (0,0)) * t1);
[/asy]](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/texer/r/rvltzlrl.png)
The larger







Previously it was observed that
![$$\mu(\mathbb{T}) \lesssim \mu(\mathbb{T}[T_\rho])\mu(\mathbb{T}_\rho)$$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/4/4/d/44d3278fe07f2c7fe49f50f47511848bb799e37c.png)


![$$\mu(\mathbb{T}) \lesssim \mu(\mathbb{T}[T_\rho]) \cdot \mu(G)$$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/6/4/7/6474451bfb52cb37afa906d67cd1d765f83385c2.png)




If you feel that










satisfies the KTW axioms, i.e.
for all
, and
- For every
,
"satisfies the FW axioms after rescaling", i.e. for every
, we have
.
That's it for my overview. Happy

This post has been edited 4 times. Last edited by greenturtle3141, Mar 15, 2025, 6:47 AM