Difference between revisions of "Zorn's Lemma"

m (Inserted a missing subscript 'i' in 'X_i'.)
m (Proof (using the Axiom of Choice): corrected "union" to "intersection" in the definition of M before Lemma 1)
 
(2 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown)
Line 24: Line 24:
 
* For every totally ordered subset <math>T \subseteq B</math>, the least upper bound of <math>T</math> in <math>A'</math> is an element of <math>B</math>.
 
* For every totally ordered subset <math>T \subseteq B</math>, the least upper bound of <math>T</math> in <math>A'</math> is an element of <math>B</math>.
  
Let <math>M</math> be the union of all admissable subsets of <math>A'</math>.  We note that <math>M</math> is not empty, as <math>A'</math> is an admissable subset of itself, and all admissable sets contain <math>a</math>.  Then <math>M</math> is the least admissable set, under order by inclusion.
+
Let <math>M</math> be the intersection of all admissable subsets of <math>A'</math>.  We note that <math>M</math> is not empty, as <math>A'</math> is an admissable subset of itself, and all admissable sets contain <math>a</math>.  Then <math>M</math> is the least admissable set, under order by inclusion.
  
 
We say that an element <math>c \in M</math> is an ''extreme point'' if <math>x\in M</math>, <math>x < c</math> together imply <math>f(x) \le c</math>.  For an extreme point <math>c</math> denote by <math>M_c</math> the set of <math>x\in M</math> such that <math>x \le c</math> or <math>f(c) \le x</math>.
 
We say that an element <math>c \in M</math> is an ''extreme point'' if <math>x\in M</math>, <math>x < c</math> together imply <math>f(x) \le c</math>.  For an extreme point <math>c</math> denote by <math>M_c</math> the set of <math>x\in M</math> such that <math>x \le c</math> or <math>f(c) \le x</math>.
Line 42: Line 42:
 
''Proof.'' Let <math>E</math> be the set of extreme points of <math>M</math>.  As before, it suffices to show that <math>E</math> is an admissable set.  Evidently, <math>a</math> is an extreme point of <math>M</math>, as no element of <math>M</math> is less than <math>a</math>, so every element less than <math>a</math> is also less than or equal to <math>f(a)</math>.  Now, suppose <math>c</math> is an extreme point of <math>M</math>.  Then for any <math>x\in M</math>, if <math>x < f(c)</math>, then by Lemma 1, <math>x\le c</math>.  If <math>x=c</math>, then <math>f(x) = f(c)</math>, so <math>f(x) \le f(c)</math>; if <math>x<c</math>, then since <math>c</math> is an extreme point, <math>f(x) \le c \le f(c)</math>.  Therefore <math>f(c)</math> is an extreme point, so <math>f(E) \subseteq E</math>.
 
''Proof.'' Let <math>E</math> be the set of extreme points of <math>M</math>.  As before, it suffices to show that <math>E</math> is an admissable set.  Evidently, <math>a</math> is an extreme point of <math>M</math>, as no element of <math>M</math> is less than <math>a</math>, so every element less than <math>a</math> is also less than or equal to <math>f(a)</math>.  Now, suppose <math>c</math> is an extreme point of <math>M</math>.  Then for any <math>x\in M</math>, if <math>x < f(c)</math>, then by Lemma 1, <math>x\le c</math>.  If <math>x=c</math>, then <math>f(x) = f(c)</math>, so <math>f(x) \le f(c)</math>; if <math>x<c</math>, then since <math>c</math> is an extreme point, <math>f(x) \le c \le f(c)</math>.  Therefore <math>f(c)</math> is an extreme point, so <math>f(E) \subseteq E</math>.
  
Now, let <math>T</math> be a totally ordered set of extreme points.  Consider the least upper bound <math>s</math> of <math>T</math> in <math>M</math>.  If <math>x</math> is an element of <math>M</math> strictly less than <math>s</math>, then <math>s</math> must be strictly less than some element <math>c \in T</math>.  But <math>c</math> is an extreme point, so <math>f(x) \le c \le s</math>.  Therefore <math>s</math> is an extreme point, i.e., an element of <math>E</math>.  It follows that <math>E</math> is an admissable set, so as before, <math>E=M</math>.  {{halmos}}
+
Now, let <math>T</math> be a totally ordered set of extreme points.  Consider the least upper bound <math>s</math> of <math>T</math> in <math>M</math>.  If <math>x</math> is an element of <math>M</math> strictly less than <math>s</math>, then <math>x</math> must be strictly less than some element <math>c \in T</math>.  But <math>c</math> is an extreme point, so <math>f(x) \le c \le s</math>.  Therefore <math>s</math> is an extreme point, i.e., an element of <math>E</math>.  It follows that <math>E</math> is an admissable set, so as before, <math>E=M</math>.  {{halmos}}
  
 
=== Theorem 3 (Bourbaki). ===
 
=== Theorem 3 (Bourbaki). ===
Line 68: Line 68:
 
is evidently the least upper bound of the <math>X_i</math>, and if <math>a,b \in Z</math>, then for some <math>i,j \in I</math>, <math>a \in X_i</math> and <math>b \in X_j</math>; one of <math>X_i</math> and <math>X_j</math> is a subset of the other, by assumption, so <math>a</math> and <math>b</math> are comparable.  It follows that <math>Z</math> is totally ordered, i.e., <math>Z \in T</math>.
 
is evidently the least upper bound of the <math>X_i</math>, and if <math>a,b \in Z</math>, then for some <math>i,j \in I</math>, <math>a \in X_i</math> and <math>b \in X_j</math>; one of <math>X_i</math> and <math>X_j</math> is a subset of the other, by assumption, so <math>a</math> and <math>b</math> are comparable.  It follows that <math>Z</math> is totally ordered, i.e., <math>Z \in T</math>.
  
Now, by Corollary 4, there exists a maximal element <math>P</math> of <math>Z</math>.  This set <math>P</math> is totally ordered, so it has an upper bound <math>x_0</math> in <math>A</math>.  Then <math>P \cup \{x_0\}</math> is a totally ordered set, so by the maximality of <math>P</math>, <math>x_0 \in P</math>.  Now, if <math>y\ge x_0</math>, then <math>P \cup \{y\}</math> is a totally ordered set, so <math>y \in P</math> and <math>y\le x_0</math>, so <math>y=x_0</math>.  Therefore <math>x_0</math> is a maximal element, as desired.  {{halmos}}
+
Now, by Corollary 4, there exists a maximal element <math>P</math> of <math>T</math>.  This set <math>P</math> is totally ordered, so it has an upper bound <math>x_0</math> in <math>A</math>.  Then <math>P \cup \{x_0\}</math> is a totally ordered set, so by the maximality of <math>P</math>, <math>x_0 \in P</math>.  Now, if <math>y\ge x_0</math>, then <math>P \cup \{y\}</math> is a totally ordered set, so <math>y \in P</math> and <math>y\le x_0</math>, so <math>y=x_0</math>.  Therefore <math>x_0</math> is a maximal element, as desired.  {{halmos}}
  
 
== References ==
 
== References ==

Latest revision as of 18:02, 1 August 2018

Zorn's Lemma is a set theoretic result which is equivalent to the Axiom of Choice.

Background

Let $A$ be a partially ordered set.

We say that $A$ is inductively ordered if every totally ordered subset $T$ of $A$ has an upper bound, i.e., an element $a \in A$ such that for all $x\in T$, $x \le a$. We say that $A$ is strictly inductively ordered if every totally ordered subset $T$ of $A$ has a least upper bound, i.e., an upper bound $a$ so that if $b$ is an upper bound of $T$, then $a \le b$.

An element $m \in A$ is maximal if the relation $a \ge m$ implies $a=m$. (Note that a set may have several maximal elements.)

We say a function $f : A \to A$ is increasing if $x \le f(x)$ for all $x\in A$.

Statement

Every inductively ordered set $A$ has a maximal element.

Proof (using the Axiom of Choice)

We first prove some intermediate results, viz., Bourbaki's Theorem (also known as the Bourbaki-Witt theorem).

Let $A$ be a strictly inductively ordered set, and let $f: A \to A$ be an increasing function. Pick some $a \in A$. Let $A'$ be the set of elements $x \in A$ such that $a \le A$. Evidently, $A'$ is stricty inductively ordered, for if $T$ is a totally ordered subset of $A'$, then it has a least upper bound in $A$, which is evidently greater than $a$, so this least upper bound is an element of $A'$. We say that a subset $B \subseteq A'$ is admissable if it satisfies these conditions:

  • $a\in B$
  • $f(B) \subseteq B$
  • For every totally ordered subset $T \subseteq B$, the least upper bound of $T$ in $A'$ is an element of $B$.

Let $M$ be the intersection of all admissable subsets of $A'$. We note that $M$ is not empty, as $A'$ is an admissable subset of itself, and all admissable sets contain $a$. Then $M$ is the least admissable set, under order by inclusion.

We say that an element $c \in M$ is an extreme point if $x\in M$, $x < c$ together imply $f(x) \le c$. For an extreme point $c$ denote by $M_c$ the set of $x\in M$ such that $x \le c$ or $f(c) \le x$.

Lemma 1.

For each extreme point $c$, $M_c = M$.

Proof. It suffices to show that $M_c$ is an admissable set. Evidently, $a\le c$, so $a \in M_c$. Now, let $x$ be an element of $M_c$. If $x = c$, then evidently, $f(c) \le f(x)$, so $f(x) \in M_c$. If $x < c$, then since $c$ is an extreme point, $f(x)\le c$, so $f(x) \in M_c$. On the other hand, if $f(c) \le x$, then $f(c) \le x \le f(x)$, so $f(x) \in M_c$. Therefore $f(M_c) \subseteq M_c$.

Let $T$ be a totally ordered subset of $M_c$. Then $T$ has a least upper bound $s\in A'$. Since $M$ is admissable, $s\in M$. Now, if $s \le c$, then evidently $s\in M_c$. On the other hand, if $s\ge c$, then either $f(c) \le s$, or every element of $T$ is less than or equal to $c$, so $s \le c$. Hence the least upper bound of every totally ordered subset $T$ of $M_c$ is an element of $M_c$, so $M_c$ is admissable. Therefore $M \subseteq M_c$; since we know $M_c \subseteq M$, it follows that $M= M_c$.

Lemma 2.

Every element of $M$ is an extreme point.

Proof. Let $E$ be the set of extreme points of $M$. As before, it suffices to show that $E$ is an admissable set. Evidently, $a$ is an extreme point of $M$, as no element of $M$ is less than $a$, so every element less than $a$ is also less than or equal to $f(a)$. Now, suppose $c$ is an extreme point of $M$. Then for any $x\in M$, if $x < f(c)$, then by Lemma 1, $x\le c$. If $x=c$, then $f(x) = f(c)$, so $f(x) \le f(c)$; if $x<c$, then since $c$ is an extreme point, $f(x) \le c \le f(c)$. Therefore $f(c)$ is an extreme point, so $f(E) \subseteq E$.

Now, let $T$ be a totally ordered set of extreme points. Consider the least upper bound $s$ of $T$ in $M$. If $x$ is an element of $M$ strictly less than $s$, then $x$ must be strictly less than some element $c \in T$. But $c$ is an extreme point, so $f(x) \le c \le s$. Therefore $s$ is an extreme point, i.e., an element of $E$. It follows that $E$ is an admissable set, so as before, $E=M$.

Theorem 3 (Bourbaki).

For any strictly inductively ordered set $A$ and any increasing function $f: A \to A$, there exists an element $x_0$ of $A$ such that $x_0 = f(x_0)$.

Proof. Choose an arbitrary $a\in A$, and define $A'$ as before. Let $M$ be the least admissable subset of $A'$, as before. By Lemmata 2 and 1, for all elements $a,b \in M$, either $a \le b$, or $b \le f(b) \le a$. Therefore $M$ is totally ordered under the ordering induced by $A$. Then $M$ has a least upper bound $x_0$ which is an element of $M$. We note that $f(x_0) \in M$, so $f(x_0) \le x_0$, and since $f$ is increasing, $x_0 \le f(x_0)$. Hence $x_0 = f(x_0)$, as desired.

Note that thus far, we have not used the Axiom of Choice. In the next corollary, however, we will use the Axiom of Choice.

Corollary 4.

Let $A$ be a strictly inductively ordered set. Then $A$ has a maximal element.

Proof. Suppose the contrary. Then by the Axiom of Choice, for each $x \in A$, we may define $f(x)$ to be an element strictly greater than $x$. Then $f$ is an increasing function, but for no $x \in A$ does $x = f(x)$, which contradicts the Bourbaki-Witt Theorem.

Corollary 5 (Zorn's Lemma).

Let $A$ be an inductively ordered set. Then $A$ has a maximal element.

Proof. Let $T$ be the family of totally ordered subsets of $A$.

We claim that under the order relation $\subseteq$, $T$ is a strictly inductively ordered set. Indeed, if $\{ X_i \}_{i\in I}$ is a totally ordered subset of $T$, then \[Z = \bigcup_{i\in I} X_i\] is evidently the least upper bound of the $X_i$, and if $a,b \in Z$, then for some $i,j \in I$, $a \in X_i$ and $b \in X_j$; one of $X_i$ and $X_j$ is a subset of the other, by assumption, so $a$ and $b$ are comparable. It follows that $Z$ is totally ordered, i.e., $Z \in T$.

Now, by Corollary 4, there exists a maximal element $P$ of $T$. This set $P$ is totally ordered, so it has an upper bound $x_0$ in $A$. Then $P \cup \{x_0\}$ is a totally ordered set, so by the maximality of $P$, $x_0 \in P$. Now, if $y\ge x_0$, then $P \cup \{y\}$ is a totally ordered set, so $y \in P$ and $y\le x_0$, so $y=x_0$. Therefore $x_0$ is a maximal element, as desired.

References

  • Lang, S. Algebra, Revised Third Edition. Springer (2002), ISBN 0-387-95385-X.

See Also