Difference between revisions of "Zermelo-Fraenkel Axioms"
(linkage) |
(Improved statements of axioms and discussion of AC) |
||
Line 5: | Line 5: | ||
This axiom establishes the most basic property of sets - a set is completely characterized by its elements alone. <br/> | This axiom establishes the most basic property of sets - a set is completely characterized by its elements alone. <br/> | ||
− | '''Statement:''' | + | '''Statement:''' Two sets <math>A</math> and <math>B</math> are equal if and only if the statements <math>a \in A</math> (<math>a</math> is an element of <math>A</math>) and <math>b\in B</math> (<math>b</math> is an element of <math>B</math>) are equivalent. |
− | === The | + | === The Empty Set Axiom === |
This axiom ensures that there is at least one set. <br/> | This axiom ensures that there is at least one set. <br/> | ||
− | '''Statement:''' There exists a set called the | + | '''Statement:''' There exists a set (called the [[empty set]] and denoted <math>\varnothing</math>) which contains no elements. |
=== The Axiom of Subset Selection === | === The Axiom of Subset Selection === | ||
Line 20: | Line 20: | ||
This axiom allows us to construct a bigger set from a given set. <br/> | This axiom allows us to construct a bigger set from a given set. <br/> | ||
− | '''Statement:''' | + | '''Statement:''' For every set <math>A</math>, there exists a set, called the [[power set]] of <math>A</math> (denoted <math>\mathcal{P}(A)</math> or <math>\mathfrak{P}(A)</math>), containing exactly the [[subset]]s of <math>A</math>. |
=== The Axiom of Replacement === | === The Axiom of Replacement === | ||
This axiom allows us, given a set, to construct other sets of the same size. <br/> | This axiom allows us, given a set, to construct other sets of the same size. <br/> | ||
− | '''Statement:''' Given a set <math>A</math> and a [[ | + | '''Statement:''' Given a set <math>A</math> and a [[functional predicate]] in the language of set theory, there is a set which consists of exactly those elements related to elements in <math>A</math>. |
=== The Axiom of Union === | === The Axiom of Union === | ||
Line 35: | Line 35: | ||
This gives us at least one infinite set. <br/> | This gives us at least one infinite set. <br/> | ||
− | '''Statement:''' There exists a set <math>A</math> | + | '''Statement:''' There exists an infinite set, i.e., a set <math>A</math> and an [[injection]] <math>A \to A</math> which is not bijective. |
=== The Axiom of Foundation === | === The Axiom of Foundation === | ||
This makes sure no set contains itself, thus avoiding certain paradoxical situations. <br/> | This makes sure no set contains itself, thus avoiding certain paradoxical situations. <br/> | ||
− | '''Statement:''' The relation ''belongs to'' is [[well-founded]]. | + | '''Statement:''' The relation ''belongs to'' is [[well-founded]]. In other words, for every nonempty set <math>A</math>, there exists a set <math>a \in A</math> which is disjoint from <math>A</math>. |
=== The Axiom of Choice === | === The Axiom of Choice === | ||
This allows to find a choice set for any arbitrary collection of sets. <br/> | This allows to find a choice set for any arbitrary collection of sets. <br/> | ||
− | '''Statement:''' | + | '''Statement:''' For each collection of [[disjoint sets]], there exists a set (called the choice set) containing precisely one element of each set in the collection. |
− | + | This axiom is more controversial than the others. It gives no new results when applied to finite sets, but for infinite sets, it results in certain surprising results such as the [[Banach-Tarski Paradox]]. As a result, many mathematicians investigate what parts of mathematics can be obtained without the axiom of choice, which results of mathematics require the axiom of choices, and plausible negations of the axiom of choice. | |
==See Also== | ==See Also== |
Revision as of 11:14, 26 January 2008
The Zermelo-Fraenkel Axioms are a set of axioms that compiled by Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel that make it very convenient for set theorists to determine whether a given collection of objects with a given property describable by the language of set theory could be called a set. As shown by paradoxes such as Russell's Paradox, some restrictions must be put on which collections to call sets.
Contents
Axioms
The Axiom of Extensionability
This axiom establishes the most basic property of sets - a set is completely characterized by its elements alone.
Statement: Two sets and are equal if and only if the statements ( is an element of ) and ( is an element of ) are equivalent.
The Empty Set Axiom
This axiom ensures that there is at least one set.
Statement: There exists a set (called the empty set and denoted ) which contains no elements.
The Axiom of Subset Selection
This axiom declares subsets of a given set as sets themselves.
Statement: Given a set , and a formula with one free variable, there exists a set whose elements are precisely those elements of which satisfy .
The Power Set Axiom
This axiom allows us to construct a bigger set from a given set.
Statement: For every set , there exists a set, called the power set of (denoted or ), containing exactly the subsets of .
The Axiom of Replacement
This axiom allows us, given a set, to construct other sets of the same size.
Statement: Given a set and a functional predicate in the language of set theory, there is a set which consists of exactly those elements related to elements in .
The Axiom of Union
This axiom allows us to take unions of two or more sets.
Statement: Given a set , there exists a set with exactly those elements which belong to some element of .
The Axiom of Infinity
This gives us at least one infinite set.
Statement: There exists an infinite set, i.e., a set and an injection which is not bijective.
The Axiom of Foundation
This makes sure no set contains itself, thus avoiding certain paradoxical situations.
Statement: The relation belongs to is well-founded. In other words, for every nonempty set , there exists a set which is disjoint from .
The Axiom of Choice
This allows to find a choice set for any arbitrary collection of sets.
Statement: For each collection of disjoint sets, there exists a set (called the choice set) containing precisely one element of each set in the collection.
This axiom is more controversial than the others. It gives no new results when applied to finite sets, but for infinite sets, it results in certain surprising results such as the Banach-Tarski Paradox. As a result, many mathematicians investigate what parts of mathematics can be obtained without the axiom of choice, which results of mathematics require the axiom of choices, and plausible negations of the axiom of choice.