|
|
Line 1: |
Line 1: |
| | | |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |
− |
| |
− | Main menu
| |
− |
| |
− | WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
| |
− | Search Wikipedia
| |
− | Search
| |
− | Donate
| |
− | Create account
| |
− | Log in
| |
− |
| |
− | Personal tools
| |
− | Contents hide
| |
− | (Top)
| |
− | History
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | References
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem
| |
− |
| |
− | Article
| |
− | Talk
| |
− | Read
| |
− | Edit
| |
− | View history
| |
− |
| |
− | Tools
| |
− | Appearance hide
| |
− | Text
| |
− |
| |
− | Small
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Large
| |
− | Width
| |
− |
| |
− | Standard
| |
− |
| |
− | Wide
| |
− | Color (beta)
| |
− |
| |
− | Automatic
| |
− |
| |
− | Light
| |
− |
| |
− | Dark
| |
− | From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
| |
− |
| |
− | This article may be too technical for most readers to understand. Please help improve it to make it understandable to non-experts, without removing the technical details. (June 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
| |
− | In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.
| |
− |
| |
− | History
| |
− | The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved in ATR0 (a second-order arithmetic theory with a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion).
| |
− |
| |
− | In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function, which dwarfs
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}. A finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.
| |
− |
| |
− | Statement
| |
− | The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.
| |
− |
| |
− | Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.
| |
− |
| |
− | Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write
| |
− | T
| |
− | 1
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{1}\leq T_{2}} if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that:
| |
− |
| |
− | For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)};
| |
− | If w is any successor of v in T1, then
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w)} is a successor of
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}; and
| |
− | If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{1})} to
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | w
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(w_{2})} in T2 contains
| |
− | F
| |
− | (
| |
− | v
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle F(v)}.
| |
− | Kruskal's tree theorem then states:
| |
− |
| |
− | If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j} so that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}}.)
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman's work
| |
− | For a countable label set X, Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where X has size one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[1] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[2] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[3] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[4][5] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
| |
− | 1-CA0.
| |
− |
| |
− | Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[6]
| |
− |
| |
− | Weak tree function
| |
− | Suppose that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is the statement:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is some m such that if T1, ..., Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Ti has
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, then
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} for some
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j}.
| |
− | All the statements
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} is true for all n".[7] Moreover, the length of the shortest proof of
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function, for example.[citation needed] The least m for which
| |
− | P
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle P(n)} holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.
| |
− |
| |
− | Define
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(n)}, the weak tree function, as the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of unlabeled rooted trees, where each Ti has at most
| |
− | i
| |
− | +
| |
− | n
| |
− | {\displaystyle i+n} vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | It is known that
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 2
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(1)=2},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 5
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(2)=5},
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≥
| |
− | 844
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 424
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 930
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 131
| |
− | ,
| |
− | 960
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(3)\geq 844,424,930,131,960} (about 844 trillion),
| |
− | tree
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | ≫
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{tree}}(4)\gg g_{64}} (where
| |
− | g
| |
− | 64
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{64}} is Graham's number), and
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | t
| |
− | r
| |
− | e
| |
− | e
| |
− | 8
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 7
| |
− | )
| |
− | .
| |
− | {\displaystyle \mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{\mathrm {tree} ^{8}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7)}(7).}
| |
− |
| |
− | To differentiate the two functions, "TREE" (with all caps) is the big TREE function, and "tree" (with all letters in lowercase) is the weak tree function.
| |
− |
| |
− | TREE function
| |
− | Sequence of trees where each node is colored either green, red, blue
| |
− | A sequence of rooted trees labelled from a set of 3 labels (blue < red < green). The nth tree in the sequence contains at most n vertices, and no tree is inf-embeddable within any later tree in the sequence. TREE(3) is defined to be the longest possible length of such a sequence.
| |
− | By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | n
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(n)}[a] to be the largest m so that we have the following:
| |
− |
| |
− | There is a sequence T1, ..., Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that
| |
− | T
| |
− | i
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | T
| |
− | j
| |
− | {\displaystyle T_{i}\leq T_{j}} does not hold for any
| |
− | i
| |
− | <
| |
− | j
| |
− | ≤
| |
− | m
| |
− | {\displaystyle i<j\leq m}.
| |
− | The TREE sequence begins
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 1
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(1)=1},
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(2)=3}, then suddenly,
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)} explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)},
| |
− | n
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 5
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n^{n(5)}(5)}, and Graham's number,[b] are extremely small by comparison. A lower bound for
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 4
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(4)}, and, hence, an extremely weak lower bound for
| |
− | TREE
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle {\text{TREE}}(3)}, is
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}.[c][9] Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound
| |
− | A
| |
− | A
| |
− | (
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | )
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | {\displaystyle A^{A(187196)}(1)}, which is approximately
| |
− | g
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 187196
| |
− | 3
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{3\uparrow ^{187196}3}}, where
| |
− | g
| |
− | x
| |
− | {\displaystyle g_{x}} is Graham's function.
| |
− |
| |
− | See also
| |
− | Paris–Harrington theorem
| |
− | Kanamori–McAloon theorem
| |
− | Robertson–Seymour theorem
| |
− | Notes
| |
− | ^ a Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
| |
− | ^ b n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 1
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 3
| |
− | ,
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 2
| |
− | )
| |
− | =
| |
− | 11
| |
− | ,
| |
− | and
| |
− | n
| |
− | (
| |
− | 3
| |
− | )
| |
− | >
| |
− | 2
| |
− | ↑
| |
− | 7197
| |
− | 158386
| |
− | {\displaystyle n(1)=3,n(2)=11,\,{\textrm {and}}\,n(3)>2\uparrow ^{7197}158386}.
| |
− | ^ c A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)).
| |
− | References
| |
− | Citations
| |
− |
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
| |
− | Friedman 2002, p. 60
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
| |
− | Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
| |
− | Marcone 2001, pp. 8–9
| |
− | Rathjen & Weiermann 1993.
| |
− | Smith 1985, p. 120
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
| |
− | Bibliography
| |
− |
| |
− | Friedman, Harvey M. (2002). "Internal finite tree embeddings". In Sieg, Wilfried; Feferman, Solomon (eds.). Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: essays in honor of Solomon Feferman. Lecture notes in logic. Vol. 15. Natick, Mass: AK Peters. pp. 60–91. ISBN 978-1-56881-170-3. MR 1943303.
| |
− | H. Gallier, Jean (September 1991). "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 53 (3): 199–260. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E. MR 1129778.
| |
− | Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960). "Well-Quasi-Ordering, The Tree Theorem, and Vazsonyi's Conjecture" (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 95 (2). American Mathematical Society: 210–225. doi:10.2307/1993287. JSTOR 1993287. MR 0111704.
| |
− | Marcone, Alberto (2005). Simpson, Stephen G. (ed.). "WQO and BQO theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Logic. 21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 303–330. doi:10.1017/9781316755846.020. ISBN 978-1-316-75584-6.
| |
− | Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (October 1963). "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees" (PDF). Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 59 (4): 833–835. Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0153601. S2CID 251095188.
| |
− | Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (February 1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem" (PDF). Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G. MR 1212407.
| |
− | Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 87–117. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | Smith, Rick L. (1985). "The Consistency Strengths of Some Finite Forms of the Higman and Kruskal Theorems". In Friedman, Harvey; Harrington, L. A. (eds.). Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Vol. 117. Amsterdam ; New York: North-Holland. pp. 119–136. doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(09)70157-0. ISBN 978-0-444-87834-2.
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Large numbers
| |
− | vte
| |
− | Order theory
| |
− | Categories: Mathematical logicOrder theoryTheorems in discrete mathematicsTrees (graph theory)Wellfoundedness
| |
− | This page was last edited on 21 October 2024, at 22:33 (UTC).
| |
− | Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
| |
− | Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaCode of ConductDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementMobile view
| |
− | Wikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki
| |