Difference between revisions of "Russell's Paradox"

 
(expand)
Line 1: Line 1:
This paradox, due to Bertrand Russell, was one of those which forced the axiomatization of set theory. We start with the property <math>P</math>: (<math>x</math> does not belong to <math>x</math>). We define <math>C</math> to be the collection of all <math>x</math> with the property <math>P</math>. Now comes the question: does <math>C</math> have the property <math>P</math>? Assuming it does, it cannot be in itself, in spite of satisfying its own membership criterion, a contradiction. Assuming it doesn't, it must be in itself, in spite of not satisfying its own membership criterion. This is the paradox.
+
'''Russell's Paradox''', creditted to Bertrand Russell, was one of those which forced the axiomatization of set theory.  
 +
 
 +
==Paradox==
 +
We start with the property <math>P</math>: (<math>x</math> does not belong to <math>x</math>). We define <math>C</math> to be the collection of all <math>x</math> with the property <math>P</math>. Now comes the question: does <math>C</math> have the property <math>P</math>? Assuming it does, it cannot be in itself, in spite of satisfying its own membership criterion, a contradiction. Assuming it doesn't, it must be in itself, in spite of not satisfying its own membership criterion. This is the paradox.
 +
 
 +
==See Also==
 +
*[[Set]]
 +
 
 +
[[Category:Set theory]]

Revision as of 18:41, 24 November 2007

Russell's Paradox, creditted to Bertrand Russell, was one of those which forced the axiomatization of set theory.

Paradox

We start with the property $P$: ($x$ does not belong to $x$). We define $C$ to be the collection of all $x$ with the property $P$. Now comes the question: does $C$ have the property $P$? Assuming it does, it cannot be in itself, in spite of satisfying its own membership criterion, a contradiction. Assuming it doesn't, it must be in itself, in spite of not satisfying its own membership criterion. This is the paradox.

See Also