The Hales-Jewett theorem
by liberator, Apr 2, 2018, 7:50 PM
This is just some stuff I've been looking at recently.
In this blog post, we will discuss the powerful Hales-Jewett theorem, one of the central results of Ramsey theory. We use it to prove the famous van der Waerden theorem, as well as its
-dimensional generalisation, Gallai's theorem.
1. Definitions and Examples
For any positive integer
, we write
. Given a finite set
, we denote by
the
-dimensional hypercube on the alphabet
; that is, the set of all possible
-tuples
, with
.
A
-colouring of
is a map
; that is, we assign each element of
one of
colours, labelled by the elements of
.
A subset
of
is called a combinatorial line if there exists a non-empty set of indices
and, for each
, an
such that
We call
the set of active coordinates of
, since these are the coordinates that vary: the others are "fixed". More informally, a combinatorial line is the set of
-tuples we get when we fix the values of some of the components, and set the other components equal to each other, allowing this common value to vary among the elements of
.
For example, in
, we have the following combinatorial lines:
Displayed more pictorially,
![[asy]
unitsize(1cm);
real e = 0.5;
for (int x=0; x<=2; ++x) {
for (int y=0; y<=2; ++y) {
label("$("+string(3-y)+","+string(x+1)+")$",(x,y));
}
}
DPA((-e,2)--(2+e,2)^^(-e,1)--(2+e,1)^^(-e,0)--(2+e,0),red);
DPA((0,-e)--(0,2+e)^^(1,-e)--(1,2+e)^^(2,-e)--(2,2+e),blue);
DPA((-e,2+e)--(2+e,-e),green);
[/asy]](//latex.artofproblemsolving.com/7/e/9/7e9f459fa7d9b7d81c5d10db2d6a7d918f6693d9.png)
Visual representations of combinatorial lines can be good when
; however, for
, I find them less useful, essentially because I struggle to visualise in
or more dimensions
.
Consider the standard "product order" on
, given by
for all
. If we restrict our attention to a combinatorial line, this partial order
is in fact a total order. Thus given a combinatorial line
, we define
to be the last element in our ordering of
and
to be the first element.
Given a
-colouring of
and a positive integer
, a rainbow
-windmill is a set of
combinatorial lines
such that
, a homothetic copy of
is a set of the form
, where
and
. Geometrically, we are enlarging the set
by a positive integer scale factor from the origin, then translating the enlarged image by some vector in
. As an example, when
, a homothetic copy of
is an arithmetic progression of length
.
2. The Theorem
We are now ready to state the main result of this post.
Theorem. [Hales-Jewett] Given
, there exists
such that for any
-colouring of
, there is a monochromatic combinatorial line.
The smallest such
with the desired property is denoted by
.
Proof. We go by induction on
; the base case
is trivial. Now consider the following claim:
Claim. For
, there exists
such that for any
-colouring of
, there is either a monochromatic combinatorial line or a rainbow
-windmill.
Note that our theorem follows from this claim: take
, and look at the colour of the focus of the rainbow
-windmill.
We prove our claim by induction on
. For the base case
, take
. Now assume that
works for
; we show that
, where
, works for
.
Suppose that we have
-coloured
such that there are no monochromatic combinatorial lines. Note that
is isomorphic to
. There are
possible
-colourings of
, so by our choice of
, there is a (monochromatic) combinatorial line
in
, with active coordinate set
, such that for any
and
, the colour of
in our
-colouring of
is the same as the color of
in the
-colouring of
.
Now take a rainbow
-windmill
for our
-colouring of
. Suppose the respective active coordinate sets are
, and let
be the focus. For each
, let
be the combinatorial line through the point
and with active coordinate set
. Then
is a rainbow
-windmill with focus
. Combining this with the combinatorial line through the point
with active coordinate set
gives us the desired rainbow
-windmill.
This completes the proof of the claim, and hence of the theorem.
3. Applications
We now see how the Hales-Jewett theorem can be used to prove van der Waerden's theorem and Gallai's theorem easily.
Theorem. [van der Waerden] Given
, there exists
such that for any
-colouring of
, there is a monochromatic arithmetic progression of length
.
Proof. Given a
-colouring
of
, consider the
-colouring
of
, with
sufficiently large, given by
By the Hales-Jewett theorem, there is a monochromatic combinatorial line in
, which corresponds to an arithmetic progression of length
in
. Explicitly, if
is the set of active coordinates of our combinatorial line, then our arithmetic progression is
where
. 
Gallai's theorem is essentially a generalisation of van der Waerden's theorem to
. Recall that a homothetic copy of
is a set of the form
, where
and
.
Theorem. [Gallai] Given a finite set
, for any
-colouring of
, there exists a monochromatic homothetic copy of
.
Proof. Let
. Given a
-colouring
of
, consider the
-colouring
of
, with
sufficiently large, given by
By the Hales-Jewett theorem, there is a monochromatic combinatorial line in
, which corresponds to a monochromatic homothetic copy of
in
. Explicitly, if
is the set of active coordinates of our combinatorial line, then our homothetic copy of
is
. 
In this blog post, we will discuss the powerful Hales-Jewett theorem, one of the central results of Ramsey theory. We use it to prove the famous van der Waerden theorem, as well as its

1. Definitions and Examples
For any positive integer

![$[n]=\{1,2,\dots,n\}$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/2/d/c/2dcf88ff3802f283c8e9760b28bc41fbf2dcb443.png)







A


![$X^n\to[k]$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/f/d/3/fd35604f77c0b255ab5eb9545bada0d0dc5436de.png)


![$[k]$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/8/c/a/8ca473287b9ed24a5ebf817368679882f9975c23.png)
A subset


![$I=\{i_1,i_2,\dots,i_k\}\subseteq[n]$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/2/6/a/26a4dd72743c2c7a1b8da7ac9549ed12166cb20f.png)







For example, in
![$[3]^2$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/d/c/c/dcc92542b529edd39d1adf32edfa6fc5f8c5edaa.png)

![[asy]
unitsize(1cm);
real e = 0.5;
for (int x=0; x<=2; ++x) {
for (int y=0; y<=2; ++y) {
label("$("+string(3-y)+","+string(x+1)+")$",(x,y));
}
}
DPA((-e,2)--(2+e,2)^^(-e,1)--(2+e,1)^^(-e,0)--(2+e,0),red);
DPA((0,-e)--(0,2+e)^^(1,-e)--(1,2+e)^^(2,-e)--(2,2+e),blue);
DPA((-e,2+e)--(2+e,-e),green);
[/asy]](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/7/e/9/7e9f459fa7d9b7d81c5d10db2d6a7d918f6693d9.png)
Visual representations of combinatorial lines can be good when




Consider the standard "product order" on
![$[m]^n$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/a/7/2/a721b3fb78fd06ec079fe6ea3ed0240f65c5ca77.png)







Given a

![$[m]^n$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/a/7/2/a721b3fb78fd06ec079fe6ea3ed0240f65c5ca77.png)




- There exists
such that
for all
. We call
the focus of the rainbow
-windmill.
- Each individual
is monochromatic; i.e. all the points of an
, ignoring the focus, are the same colour.
- No two
have the same colour.








![$[m]$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/6/d/8/6d823912054b318ac7c77ee09ae9dcf0245ccc8d.png)

2. The Theorem
We are now ready to state the main result of this post.
Theorem. [Hales-Jewett] Given



![$[m]^n$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/a/7/2/a721b3fb78fd06ec079fe6ea3ed0240f65c5ca77.png)
The smallest such


Proof. We go by induction on


Claim. For



![$[m]^n$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/a/7/2/a721b3fb78fd06ec079fe6ea3ed0240f65c5ca77.png)

Note that our theorem follows from this claim: take


We prove our claim by induction on








Suppose that we have

![$[m]^{n+d}$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/0/5/6/056ff1482ef1ab167ea3282cc4e633ad79ce9748.png)
![$[m]^{n+d}$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/0/5/6/056ff1482ef1ab167ea3282cc4e633ad79ce9748.png)
![$[m]^n\times[m]^d$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/9/e/c/9ec5c8ab473f413daeafe48b64a4bc793bfc6ab2.png)


![$[m]^n$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/a/7/2/a721b3fb78fd06ec079fe6ea3ed0240f65c5ca77.png)


![$[m]^d$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/3/f/7/3f7e2ad7a3b7be01f7a97da2b7941d441c801591.png)

![$a\in[m]^n$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/2/b/d/2bd11a029604dccaee3e6b0b6e2033078d6d1dd5.png)



![$[m]^{n+d}$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/0/5/6/056ff1482ef1ab167ea3282cc4e633ad79ce9748.png)


![$[m]^n$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/a/7/2/a721b3fb78fd06ec079fe6ea3ed0240f65c5ca77.png)
Now take a rainbow



![$[m]^n$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/a/7/2/a721b3fb78fd06ec079fe6ea3ed0240f65c5ca77.png)












This completes the proof of the claim, and hence of the theorem.

3. Applications
We now see how the Hales-Jewett theorem can be used to prove van der Waerden's theorem and Gallai's theorem easily.
Theorem. [van der Waerden] Given



![$[n]$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/0/d/e/0deff9086fd7840ef23860f5bc924f1d4d2d2310.png)

Proof. Given a





![$[m]^n$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/a/7/2/a721b3fb78fd06ec079fe6ea3ed0240f65c5ca77.png)


![$[m]^n$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/a/7/2/a721b3fb78fd06ec079fe6ea3ed0240f65c5ca77.png)






Gallai's theorem is essentially a generalisation of van der Waerden's theorem to





Theorem. [Gallai] Given a finite set




Proof. Let






![$[m]^n$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/a/7/2/a721b3fb78fd06ec079fe6ea3ed0240f65c5ca77.png)


![$[m]^n$](http://latex.artofproblemsolving.com/a/7/2/a721b3fb78fd06ec079fe6ea3ed0240f65c5ca77.png)





