We have your learning goals covered with Spring and Summer courses available. Enroll today!

G
Topic
First Poster
Last Poster
k a My Retirement & New Leadership at AoPS
rrusczyk   1571
N Mar 26, 2025 by SmartGroot
I write today to announce my retirement as CEO from Art of Problem Solving. When I founded AoPS 22 years ago, I never imagined that we would reach so many students and families, or that we would find so many channels through which we discover, inspire, and train the great problem solvers of the next generation. I am very proud of all we have accomplished and I’m thankful for the many supporters who provided inspiration and encouragement along the way. I'm particularly grateful to all of the wonderful members of the AoPS Community!

I’m delighted to introduce our new leaders - Ben Kornell and Andrew Sutherland. Ben has extensive experience in education and edtech prior to joining AoPS as my successor as CEO, including starting like I did as a classroom teacher. He has a deep understanding of the value of our work because he’s an AoPS parent! Meanwhile, Andrew and I have common roots as founders of education companies; he launched Quizlet at age 15! His journey from founder to MIT to technology and product leader as our Chief Product Officer traces a pathway many of our students will follow in the years to come.

Thank you again for your support for Art of Problem Solving and we look forward to working with millions more wonderful problem solvers in the years to come.

And special thanks to all of the amazing AoPS team members who have helped build AoPS. We’ve come a long way from here:IMAGE
1571 replies
rrusczyk
Mar 24, 2025
SmartGroot
Mar 26, 2025
k a March Highlights and 2025 AoPS Online Class Information
jlacosta   0
Mar 2, 2025
March is the month for State MATHCOUNTS competitions! Kudos to everyone who participated in their local chapter competitions and best of luck to all going to State! Join us on March 11th for a Math Jam devoted to our favorite Chapter competition problems! Are you interested in training for MATHCOUNTS? Be sure to check out our AMC 8/MATHCOUNTS Basics and Advanced courses.

Are you ready to level up with Olympiad training? Registration is open with early bird pricing available for our WOOT programs: MathWOOT (Levels 1 and 2), CodeWOOT, PhysicsWOOT, and ChemWOOT. What is WOOT? WOOT stands for Worldwide Online Olympiad Training and is a 7-month high school math Olympiad preparation and testing program that brings together many of the best students from around the world to learn Olympiad problem solving skills. Classes begin in September!

Do you have plans this summer? There are so many options to fit your schedule and goals whether attending a summer camp or taking online classes, it can be a great break from the routine of the school year. Check out our summer courses at AoPS Online, or if you want a math or language arts class that doesn’t have homework, but is an enriching summer experience, our AoPS Virtual Campus summer camps may be just the ticket! We are expanding our locations for our AoPS Academies across the country with 15 locations so far and new campuses opening in Saratoga CA, Johns Creek GA, and the Upper West Side NY. Check out this page for summer camp information.

Be sure to mark your calendars for the following events:
[list][*]March 5th (Wednesday), 4:30pm PT/7:30pm ET, HCSSiM Math Jam 2025. Amber Verser, Assistant Director of the Hampshire College Summer Studies in Mathematics, will host an information session about HCSSiM, a summer program for high school students.
[*]March 6th (Thursday), 4:00pm PT/7:00pm ET, Free Webinar on Math Competitions from elementary through high school. Join us for an enlightening session that demystifies the world of math competitions and helps you make informed decisions about your contest journey.
[*]March 11th (Tuesday), 4:30pm PT/7:30pm ET, 2025 MATHCOUNTS Chapter Discussion MATH JAM. AoPS instructors will discuss some of their favorite problems from the MATHCOUNTS Chapter Competition. All are welcome!
[*]March 13th (Thursday), 4:00pm PT/7:00pm ET, Free Webinar about Summer Camps at the Virtual Campus. Transform your summer into an unforgettable learning adventure! From elementary through high school, we offer dynamic summer camps featuring topics in mathematics, language arts, and competition preparation - all designed to fit your schedule and ignite your passion for learning.[/list]
Our full course list for upcoming classes is below:
All classes run 7:30pm-8:45pm ET/4:30pm - 5:45pm PT unless otherwise noted.

Introductory: Grades 5-10

Prealgebra 1 Self-Paced

Prealgebra 1
Sunday, Mar 2 - Jun 22
Friday, Mar 28 - Jul 18
Sunday, Apr 13 - Aug 10
Tuesday, May 13 - Aug 26
Thursday, May 29 - Sep 11
Sunday, Jun 15 - Oct 12
Monday, Jun 30 - Oct 20
Wednesday, Jul 16 - Oct 29

Prealgebra 2 Self-Paced

Prealgebra 2
Tuesday, Mar 25 - Jul 8
Sunday, Apr 13 - Aug 10
Wednesday, May 7 - Aug 20
Monday, Jun 2 - Sep 22
Sunday, Jun 29 - Oct 26
Friday, Jul 25 - Nov 21


Introduction to Algebra A Self-Paced

Introduction to Algebra A
Sunday, Mar 23 - Jul 20
Monday, Apr 7 - Jul 28
Sunday, May 11 - Sep 14 (1:00 - 2:30 pm ET/10:00 - 11:30 am PT)
Wednesday, May 14 - Aug 27
Friday, May 30 - Sep 26
Monday, Jun 2 - Sep 22
Sunday, Jun 15 - Oct 12
Thursday, Jun 26 - Oct 9
Tuesday, Jul 15 - Oct 28

Introduction to Counting & Probability Self-Paced

Introduction to Counting & Probability
Sunday, Mar 16 - Jun 8
Wednesday, Apr 16 - Jul 2
Thursday, May 15 - Jul 31
Sunday, Jun 1 - Aug 24
Thursday, Jun 12 - Aug 28
Wednesday, Jul 9 - Sep 24
Sunday, Jul 27 - Oct 19

Introduction to Number Theory
Monday, Mar 17 - Jun 9
Thursday, Apr 17 - Jul 3
Friday, May 9 - Aug 1
Wednesday, May 21 - Aug 6
Monday, Jun 9 - Aug 25
Sunday, Jun 15 - Sep 14
Tuesday, Jul 15 - Sep 30

Introduction to Algebra B Self-Paced

Introduction to Algebra B
Sunday, Mar 2 - Jun 22
Wednesday, Apr 16 - Jul 30
Tuesday, May 6 - Aug 19
Wednesday, Jun 4 - Sep 17
Sunday, Jun 22 - Oct 19
Friday, Jul 18 - Nov 14

Introduction to Geometry
Tuesday, Mar 4 - Aug 12
Sunday, Mar 23 - Sep 21
Wednesday, Apr 23 - Oct 1
Sunday, May 11 - Nov 9
Tuesday, May 20 - Oct 28
Monday, Jun 16 - Dec 8
Friday, Jun 20 - Jan 9
Sunday, Jun 29 - Jan 11
Monday, Jul 14 - Jan 19

Intermediate: Grades 8-12

Intermediate Algebra
Sunday, Mar 16 - Sep 14
Tuesday, Mar 25 - Sep 2
Monday, Apr 21 - Oct 13
Sunday, Jun 1 - Nov 23
Tuesday, Jun 10 - Nov 18
Wednesday, Jun 25 - Dec 10
Sunday, Jul 13 - Jan 18
Thursday, Jul 24 - Jan 22

Intermediate Counting & Probability
Sunday, Mar 23 - Aug 3
Wednesday, May 21 - Sep 17
Sunday, Jun 22 - Nov 2

Intermediate Number Theory
Friday, Apr 11 - Jun 27
Sunday, Jun 1 - Aug 24
Wednesday, Jun 18 - Sep 3

Precalculus
Sunday, Mar 16 - Aug 24
Wednesday, Apr 9 - Sep 3
Friday, May 16 - Oct 24
Sunday, Jun 1 - Nov 9
Monday, Jun 30 - Dec 8

Advanced: Grades 9-12

Olympiad Geometry
Wednesday, Mar 5 - May 21
Tuesday, Jun 10 - Aug 26

Calculus
Sunday, Mar 30 - Oct 5
Tuesday, May 27 - Nov 11
Wednesday, Jun 25 - Dec 17

Group Theory
Thursday, Jun 12 - Sep 11

Contest Preparation: Grades 6-12

MATHCOUNTS/AMC 8 Basics
Sunday, Mar 23 - Jun 15
Wednesday, Apr 16 - Jul 2
Friday, May 23 - Aug 15
Monday, Jun 2 - Aug 18
Thursday, Jun 12 - Aug 28
Sunday, Jun 22 - Sep 21
Tues & Thurs, Jul 8 - Aug 14 (meets twice a week!)

MATHCOUNTS/AMC 8 Advanced
Friday, Apr 11 - Jun 27
Sunday, May 11 - Aug 10
Tuesday, May 27 - Aug 12
Wednesday, Jun 11 - Aug 27
Sunday, Jun 22 - Sep 21
Tues & Thurs, Jul 8 - Aug 14 (meets twice a week!)

AMC 10 Problem Series
Tuesday, Mar 4 - May 20
Monday, Mar 31 - Jun 23
Friday, May 9 - Aug 1
Sunday, Jun 1 - Aug 24
Thursday, Jun 12 - Aug 28
Tuesday, Jun 17 - Sep 2
Sunday, Jun 22 - Sep 21 (1:00 - 2:30 pm ET/10:00 - 11:30 am PT)
Monday, Jun 23 - Sep 15
Tues & Thurs, Jul 8 - Aug 14 (meets twice a week!)

AMC 10 Final Fives
Sunday, May 11 - Jun 8
Tuesday, May 27 - Jun 17
Monday, Jun 30 - Jul 21

AMC 12 Problem Series
Tuesday, May 27 - Aug 12
Thursday, Jun 12 - Aug 28
Sunday, Jun 22 - Sep 21
Wednesday, Aug 6 - Oct 22

AMC 12 Final Fives
Sunday, May 18 - Jun 15

F=ma Problem Series
Wednesday, Jun 11 - Aug 27

WOOT Programs
Visit the pages linked for full schedule details for each of these programs!


MathWOOT Level 1
MathWOOT Level 2
ChemWOOT
CodeWOOT
PhysicsWOOT

Programming

Introduction to Programming with Python
Monday, Mar 24 - Jun 16
Thursday, May 22 - Aug 7
Sunday, Jun 15 - Sep 14 (1:00 - 2:30 pm ET/10:00 - 11:30 am PT)
Tuesday, Jun 17 - Sep 2
Monday, Jun 30 - Sep 22

Intermediate Programming with Python
Sunday, Jun 1 - Aug 24
Monday, Jun 30 - Sep 22

USACO Bronze Problem Series
Tuesday, May 13 - Jul 29
Sunday, Jun 22 - Sep 1

Physics

Introduction to Physics
Sunday, Mar 30 - Jun 22
Wednesday, May 21 - Aug 6
Sunday, Jun 15 - Sep 14
Monday, Jun 23 - Sep 15

Physics 1: Mechanics
Tuesday, Mar 25 - Sep 2
Thursday, May 22 - Oct 30
Monday, Jun 23 - Dec 15

Relativity
Sat & Sun, Apr 26 - Apr 27 (4:00 - 7:00 pm ET/1:00 - 4:00pm PT)
Mon, Tue, Wed & Thurs, Jun 23 - Jun 26 (meets every day of the week!)
0 replies
jlacosta
Mar 2, 2025
0 replies
Easy Geometry
pokmui9909   4
N 5 minutes ago by aidenkim119
Source: FKMO 2025 P4
Triangle $ABC$ satisfies $\overline{CA} > \overline{AB}$. Let the incenter of triangle $ABC$ be $\omega$, which touches $BC, CA, AB$ at $D, E, F$, respectively. Let $M$ be the midpoint of $BC$. Let the circle centered at $M$ passing through $D$ intersect $DE, DF$ at $P(\neq D), Q(\neq D)$, respecively. Let line $AP$ meet $BC$ at $N$, line $BP$ meet $CA$ at $L$. Prove that the three lines $EQ, FP, NL$ are concurrent.
4 replies
pokmui9909
Today at 5:18 AM
aidenkim119
5 minutes ago
Hard number theory
Hip1zzzil   13
N 7 minutes ago by GreekIdiot
Source: FKMO 2025 P6
Two positive integers $a,b$ satisfy the following two conditions:

1) $m^{2}|ab \Rightarrow m=1$
2) Integers $x,y,z,w$ exist such that $ax^{2}+by^{2}=z^{2}+w^{2}, w^{2}+z^{2}>0$.

Prove that for any positive integer $n$,
Positive integers $x,y,z,w$ exist such that $ax^{2}+by^{2}+n=z^{2}+w^{2}$.
13 replies
Hip1zzzil
Today at 5:08 AM
GreekIdiot
7 minutes ago
orz otl fr
Hip1zzzil   6
N 8 minutes ago by space10
Source: FKMO 2025 P3
An acute triangle $\bigtriangleup ABC$ is given which $BC>CA>AB$.
$I$ is the interior and the incircle of $\bigtriangleup ABC$ meets $BC, CA, AB$ at $D,E,F$. $AD$ and $BE$ meet at $P$. Let $l_{1}$ be a tangent from D to the circumcircle of $\bigtriangleup DIP$, and define $l_{2}$ and $l_{3}$ on $E$ and $F$, respectively.
Prove $l_{1},l_{2},l_{3}$ meet at one point.
6 replies
+1 w
Hip1zzzil
Yesterday at 10:23 AM
space10
8 minutes ago
Functional equations
hanzo.ei   5
N 10 minutes ago by GreekIdiot
Source: Greekldiot
Find all $f: \mathbb R_+ \rightarrow \mathbb R_+$ such that $f(xf(y)+f(x))=yf(x+yf(x)) \: \forall \: x,y \in \mathbb R_+$
5 replies
hanzo.ei
Yesterday at 4:33 PM
GreekIdiot
10 minutes ago
No more topics!
Collapsible arrangements [CMO 2018 - P1]
Amir Hossein   29
N Mar 26, 2025 by Ilikeminecraft
Source: 2018 Canadian Mathematical Olympiad - P1
Consider an arrangement of tokens in the plane, not necessarily at distinct points. We are allowed to apply a sequence of moves of the following kind: select a pair of tokens at points $A$ and $B$ and move both of them to the midpoint of $A$ and $B$.

We say that an arrangement of $n$ tokens is collapsible if it is possible to end up with all $n$ tokens at the same point after a finite number of moves. Prove that every arrangement of $n$ tokens is collapsible if and only if $n$ is a power of $2$.
29 replies
Amir Hossein
Mar 31, 2018
Ilikeminecraft
Mar 26, 2025
Collapsible arrangements [CMO 2018 - P1]
G H J
G H BBookmark kLocked kLocked NReply
Source: 2018 Canadian Mathematical Olympiad - P1
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
Amir Hossein
5452 posts
#1 • 8 Y
Y by Smita, phymaths, Math-Ninja, Davi-8191, Nymoldin, Danielzh, Adventure10, Mango247
Consider an arrangement of tokens in the plane, not necessarily at distinct points. We are allowed to apply a sequence of moves of the following kind: select a pair of tokens at points $A$ and $B$ and move both of them to the midpoint of $A$ and $B$.

We say that an arrangement of $n$ tokens is collapsible if it is possible to end up with all $n$ tokens at the same point after a finite number of moves. Prove that every arrangement of $n$ tokens is collapsible if and only if $n$ is a power of $2$.
This post has been edited 1 time. Last edited by Amir Hossein, Mar 31, 2018, 2:14 AM
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
adamov1
355 posts
#2 • 5 Y
Y by Amir Hossein, hansu, ESCmath, Adventure10, Mango247
Note that the sum of the coordinates of the points is constant, so the desired point must be the centroid.

To show that $n$ a power of $2$ works, proceed by induction on $\log_2 n$ by pairing up points and sending each pair to their midpoints, resulting in $2$ identical sets of $\frac{n}{2}$ points, which can be sent to their (identical) centroids by induction as desired.

Now if $n$ is not a power of $2$, consider the set of points consisting of $1$ copy of $(1,0)$ and $n-1$ copies of $(0,0)$. The centroid is then $(\frac{1}{n},0)$. Note that the given operation, when applied to these points, will only allow the coordinates to be reduced fractions with a denominator a power of $2$. But $n$ is not such a number, so this arrangement is not collapsible.
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
Mathdragon245
133 posts
#3 • 3 Y
Y by Amir Hossein, Adventure10, Mango247
Here's a solution very similar to the above.
The if part is identical ,so i am going to give a slightly different proof for the only if part.
We want to show that if $n$ has an odd divisor other than $1$,then there exists an arrangement of $n$ points which is not collapsible.
Let's put the tokens in the number line,more specifically put $2$ tokens at number $2$,and the next tokens in progressive powers of two one by one.Let the number where the token is located by the weight of the token.
Initially the total weight is $2^n$.
Furthermore,it is easy to see that the total weight remains invariant at every operation.
If somehow,me manage to get all the tokens end up at one single point ,then this means that there exist positive integers $t$ and $s$ such that $\frac{n \cdot t}{2^s}=2^n$ or $n \cdot t=2^{n+s}$,which is a contradiction since the $LHS$ has an odd divisor other than $1$,but the $RHS$ does not.
Hence,$n$ must be a power of two.
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
phymaths
264 posts
#4 • 2 Y
Y by Adventure10, Mango247
Amir Hossein wrote:
Consider an arrangement of tokens in the plane, not necessarily at distinct points. We are allowed to apply a sequence of moves of the following kind: select a pair of tokens at points $A$ and $B$ and move both of them to the midpoint of $A$ and $B$.

We say that an arrangement of $n$ tokens is collapsible if it is possible to end up with all $n$ tokens at the same point after a finite number of moves. Prove that every arrangement of $n$ tokens is collapsible if and only if $n$ is a power of $2$.

Nice Problem!
We set up the co-ordinate plane.
Let the weight of a token be the sum of its $x$ and $y$ coordinates.
Note that the total weight of all the tokens remains invariant.Thus if the arrangement is collapsible, the tokens will meet at point with co-ordinates $((x_1+x_2+...x_n)/n , (y_1 +y_2 +..y_n)/n)$.

Let us take an arrangement of $n$ tokens with $(n-1)$ of them at one point and $1$ token at another point.
Its easy to see that no matter what the coordinates of the point are, every time
we ' fuse' $2$ points, the new coordinates are of form $a/2^k$ .This the final point they meet will also be of this form.
Also we can choose $s$ and $t$ the coordinates of the set of $n-1$ points and the lone point such that $n$ and $(x_1 +x_2 +..x_n)$ are coprime forcing $n=2^k$ for some integer $k$.

Now we prove any arrangement of $2^k$ tokens is collapsible.
For this we proceed by Induction.
Base case is obvious.
Now we make pairs of points which is possible and fuse every pair.(Points with same coordinate fuse to become the same point).
Now we get $2^{k-1}$ packets of fused points.
Now we apply induction and on these points and thus each point's partner moves along with it throughout. Thus we can fuse all points and the arrangement is 'collapsible'.
Hence proved!


Motivation
This post has been edited 3 times. Last edited by phymaths, Apr 4, 2018, 12:49 PM
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
rkm0959
1721 posts
#5 • 2 Y
Y by Adventure10, Mango247
If $n=2^k$, $n$ tokens are obviously collapsible.

If not, note that the tokens have to meet at their centroid. Take $n-1$ copies of $(0,0)$ and one copy of $(1,0)$.
They have to meet at $(\frac{1}{n},0)$, but all locations of each token have coordinates of the form $(\frac{a}{2^k},0)$.
Therefore, $n$ must be a power of $2$ for this set of tokens to be collapsible. Done.
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
Durjoy1729
221 posts
#6 • 5 Y
Y by Digonta1729, potentialenergy, DonaldJ.Trump, Adventure10, Mango247
If part is very trivia. If $n=2^k $ we can find even number of point where they containing odd numbers of tokens.We can pair this odd number such that in every pair $2 $ elements { $2^x-(2m+1), 2m+1$} sum up at $2^x$. Repeatedly applying this proccess we can obtain at a moment such that in every points there must have$ 2^t $coins for a positive $t$.
This post has been edited 3 times. Last edited by Durjoy1729, Jan 4, 2019, 5:52 AM
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
Taha1381
816 posts
#7 • 2 Y
Y by Adventure10, Mango247
This is a Combinatorical function equation :) .First we are going to plug in some special points to see $n$ must be a power of $2$.For this we notice that if points have integer coordinate then any point achived by taking mean of points have a rational coordinate with denomiter a power of $2$.However the sum of coordinates still invarient with this moves so if one can have all the points in one place the coordinate of that point will be the mean of all $n$ points.This motivates a lot of constructions for example $n-1$ points on $(0,0)$ and one point on $(0,k)$ which quickly implies that $n$ should be a power of $2$.Now for showing every power of $2$ is collapsible we make use of induction let $n=2^k$ we induct on $k$.The base case is trivial.for inductive step split $2^{k+1}$ points into two parts with $2^k$ points.Apply the inductive hypopeties to bot now we have two position that in every of them there are $2^k$ points.Now just pair points in different positions and apply the move to each pair.
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
SixForty
1 post
#8
Y by
I'm just thinking out loud here, but this should be relatively easy to generalize, shouldn't it? By that I mean:

If, instead of utilizing pairs of tokens, a move is defined by selecting k tokens and moving all of them to their geometric centre, then we can prove that every arrangement of n tokens is collapsible if and only if n is a power of k. Correct?

In addition, we should be able to trivially extrapolate our proof to show that this is true for an arrangement of tokens in any m-dimensional space, and not just a plane. Correct?
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
babygrogu
46 posts
#9
Y by
SixForty wrote:
I'm just thinking out loud here, but this should be relatively easy to generalize, shouldn't it? By that I mean:

If, instead of utilizing pairs of tokens, a move is defined by selecting k tokens and moving all of them to their geometric centre, then we can prove that every arrangement of n tokens is collapsible if and only if n is a power of k. Correct?

In addition, we should be able to trivially extrapolate our proof to show that this is true for an arrangement of tokens in any m-dimensional space, and not just a plane. Correct?
Lemma: At some point, the tokens must be in an arrangement where exactly $\frac{n}{2}$ tokens are at 2 points if it is collapsible for every arrangement of tokens.

Proof: We know that right before the last move, the tokens must be at 3 points where there is 1 token at 1 point, another token at 1 point, and n-2 tokens at the midpoint of these. The only way to get to this state which works for every arrangement is for $\frac{n}{2}$ tokens to be at 2 points and to move points to the midpoint of these until the midpoint has n-2 tokens. This is because if there was a different way, then it wouldn't be true for every arrangement because if you moved one of the points you are using, the outcome would be different.

Since there should be n/2 tokens at 2 points, this means that n/2 tokens should also be collapsible for every arrangement. 2 tokens is clearly collapsible, so the next collapsible number of tokens for every arrangement of them can be $a_n$ where $a_1=2$, and $a_n=2a_{n-1}$, which is the same recursive formula for the powers of 2. This can be generalized for any dimension.
This post has been edited 2 times. Last edited by babygrogu, Nov 21, 2020, 7:45 PM
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
heheXD1
429 posts
#10
Y by
adamov1 wrote:
Click to reveal hidden text

"Now if $n$ is not a power of $2$, consider the set of points consisting of $1$ copy of $(1,0)$ and $n-1$ copies of $(0,0)$. The centroid is then $(\frac{1}{n},0)$. Note that the given operation, when applied to these points, will only allow the coordinates to be reduced fractions with a denominator a power of $2$. But $n$ is not such a number, so this arrangement is not collapsible." I don't quite understand the logic of this part of the solution, if you are trying to prove that any arrangement of $n$ tokens, where $n$ is not a power of 2, is non-collapsible, how can you just consider one specific example to arrive at a conclusion for any arrangement of $n$ tokens?
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
heheXD1
429 posts
#11 • 3 Y
Y by Mango247, Mango247, Mango247
Anyone??
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
508669
1040 posts
#12 • 1 Y
Y by Mango247
Amir Hossein wrote:
Consider an arrangement of tokens in the plane, not necessarily at distinct points. We are allowed to apply a sequence of moves of the following kind: select a pair of tokens at points $A$ and $B$ and move both of them to the midpoint of $A$ and $B$.

We say that an arrangement of $n$ tokens is collapsible if it is possible to end up with all $n$ tokens at the same point after a finite number of moves. Prove that every arrangement of $n$ tokens is collapsible if and only if $n$ is a power of $2$.

Nice problem.

If $n = 2^k$ for $k \in \mathbb{N}$, we induct on $k$ with $k = 1$ base case and see that if for all $k_1 \leq k$ we can make all tokens coincide, then for $n = 2^{k_1+1}$ tokens, we randomly pair up tokens and move each pair of tokens to their midpoint, and complete using induction hypothesis.

If $n$ is not a power of $2$, then we consider the usual Cartesian plane co-ordinates and place $n-1$ tokens at the origin and $1$ token at $(0,1)$. If all tokens are coinciding, then it must be at point $(0, \frac{1}{n})$ but given any moment, the co-ordinate of any point is of form $(0,  \frac{z}{2^p})$ for $(z, p) \in \mathbb{Z}_{\geq 0}$ but this means it can never be $(0, \frac{1}{n})$ which is the desired conclusion

@below khina has mentioned it, but still here you go, look at bold words below
Amir Hossein wrote:
Consider an arrangement of tokens in the plane, not necessarily at distinct points. We are allowed to apply a sequence of moves of the following kind: select a pair of tokens at points $A$ and $B$ and move both of them to the midpoint of $A$ and $B$.

We say that an arrangement of $n$ tokens is collapsible if it is possible to end up with all $n$ tokens at the same point after a finite number of moves. Prove that every arrangement of $n$ tokens is collapsible if and only if $n$ is a power of $2$.
This post has been edited 1 time. Last edited by 508669, Mar 12, 2021, 5:12 AM
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
heheXD1
429 posts
#13
Y by
@above How did you just consider one specific set up, being $n - 1$ tokens at the origin and 1 token at $(0, 1)$ and draw a conclusion about all arrangements?
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
khina
993 posts
#14 • 1 Y
Y by heheXD1
@above It asks to prove that it holds for ALL configurations if and only if $n$ is a power of $2$. What they did is prove that there exists SOME configuration when $n$ isn't a power of $2$, that doesn't work. This implies that it doesn't hold that ALL configurations work, which is what they want to prove for when $n$ isn't a power of $2$.
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
Returner
11 posts
#15
Y by
Please ??? provide a graph theory solution to these 2
P1
Suppose in a group of n people each one has at most 3 enemies
Prove that the group can be partitioned into 2 subgroups ST each member has at most 1 enemy in the subgroup to which he belongs

P2
2n people have assembled together around a circular table, each one having at most n-1 enemies and at least n friends
Show that there exists a circular arrangement of these 2n people where no hostile pair sits adjacent to each other
Please help this noob
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
heheXD1
429 posts
#16 • 1 Y
Y by Mango247
@2above OHHHHH, ty for explaining!
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
JustKeepRunning
2958 posts
#17
Y by
Imagine the tokens as points on a number line, label them $a_1, a_2, \cdots, a_k$. Notice that if $k=2^{n}$ for integer $n,$ then the algorithm for collapsing is simple: just average the two on the left, the two on the right, the remaining two on the left, the remaining two on the rights, etc. It is easy to see that all the numbers will come to be $\frac{a_1+a_2\cdots a_k}{k}$ because $k$ is a power of $2$.

We now prove that all other arrangements don't hold. An invariant is the sum, so this means that the number that all of the $a_i$ for $1\leq I\leq k$ collapse to is fixed, namely, it is $\frac{a_1+a_2+\cdots a_k}{k}$. Notice that the process given in the problem always results in averages with weights of $\frac{1}{2^c}$ for some integer on some number of $a_i$. Therefore, if $k$ is not a power of $2$(and it is easy to choose specific values of $a_i$ so that the numerator and denominator of the fraction are relatively prime, so there is no chance of the "odd" part of the denominator cancelling out) then there is no way to achieve such an average, so we are done.
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
jasperE3
11133 posts
#18
Y by
$\textbf{1. }$ Every arrangement of $n$ tokens is collapsible if $n$ is a power of $2$.
We prove this by induction.
Base case. One token is collapsible.
Inductive assumption. We have $2^{n+1}$ tokens on each of the points $S=\{(a_n,b_n)\}$.
Inductive step. We can divide $S$ into two equinumerous subsets $S_1$ and $S_2$. The $n$th element of $S_1$ and the $n$th element of $S_2$ are paired, and for each pairing, we collapse the tokens. Then it reduces to a $2^n$ token configuration. $\blacksquare$

$\textbf{2. }$ Some arrangement of $n$ tokens is not collapsible if $n$ is not a power of $2$.
Let the $n$ tokens be on the $x$-axis. Then the tokens must collapse to the point whose $x$-value is the arithmetic mean of their $x$-values. An example of where this is impossible is when all but one token is on the origin, and the other is at $(1,0)$. Then they must meet at $\left(\frac1n,0\right)$. Since we take the midpoint of any two tokens, only integral multiples of negative powers of two are achievable. However, this must mean that $\frac1n$ is of the form $\frac a{2^b}$, for $a,b\in\mathbb Z$. WLOG, $a$ is odd, so it must be $1$, and thus $n$ is a power of two, contradiction. $\blacksquare$

The proof is done. $\square$
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
Mogmog8
1080 posts
#19 • 2 Y
Y by centslordm, Danielzh
We claim by induction that powers of two are collapsible. For the base case $n=2^0,$ the result is clear. For the inductive step, assume $n=2^k$ is collapsible. Then, split $n=2^{k+1}$ into two sets of $2^k$ and collapse the sets so that half the tokens are at one point and the other half at another point. Then, through $2^k$ moves, we can move all the tokens to the midpoint of the two points by pairing off coins from the two sets.

Next, we claim that for $n$ not power of two, all arrangements such that the $x$ coordinates of the tokens are integers and their sum is not divisible by $n$ fail. Such an arrangement clearly exists. If the tokens are placed at $(x_i,y_i)$ for $1\le i\le n,$ the sum of the $x$ coordinates is an invariant so if $n$ is collapsible, each $x$ coordinate will eventually be $(x_1+\dots+x_n)/n.$ But each token can only move to coordinates of the form $x_1/2^{\alpha_1}+\dots+x_n/2^{\alpha_n}$ so $$\frac{x_1+\dots+x_n}{n}=\frac{x_1}{2^{\alpha_1}}+\dots+\frac{x_n}{2^{\alpha_n}}.$$This is absurd as the p-adic valuation of the left hand side is negative for any $p\mid n,$ $p\neq 2,$ while the p-adic valuation is non-negative for the right hand side. $\square$
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
HamstPan38825
8857 posts
#20
Y by
The answer is all powers of 2. For a construction, we can just work inductively, where we can combine all $2^{k+1}$ points into $2^k$ midpoints, each of which has two points. From there, we can repeat the construction for $k$ twice using the inductive hypothesis.

To show that the other $n$ do not work, consider the configuration where $n-1$ of the points are at $(0, 0)$ and the last one is at $(1, 0)$. As the operation does not change the sum of the coordinates, the final collapsible point must be $\left(\frac 1n, 0\right)$. But it's clear that the only points that tokens can ever reach must be of the form $\left(\frac i{2^k}, 0\right)$, but $n$ is not a power of $2$, so no token can ever reach this final point, contradiction.
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
peppapig_
279 posts
#21 • 1 Y
Y by mulberrykid
All powers of two.

Proof.
First we will prove that all non-powers of $2$ do not work. We will do this by constructing a configuration of $n$ coins that is not collapsible for some positive integer $n$ that is not a perfect power of $2$. We can do this by placing $n-1$ of the coins at the origin and the remaining coin at the point $(1,0)$. The sum of the $x$-coordinates of all of these points will always remain the same(since we are just taking the average every time we make a move on two coins), but notice that if we express all of these $x$-coordinates as fractions, their denominators must always be powers of $2$. This is a contradiction because we would like to end up with all of the $x$-coordinates being $\frac{1}{n}$, with $n$ not being a power of $2$, and therefore non-powers of $2$ do not work.

Now we will prove that all powers of $2$ work by giving a strategy to collapse all the coins. Notice that if you have two groups of coins of the same size on two different points, these coins are collapsible, since we can pair the coins and have them all end up at the midpoint of these two points. With powers of $2$, we start with $n=2^k$ groups of $1$ coin each, which we can collapse to $2^{k-1}$ groups of $2$ coins each, and so on and so forth until we end up with one group of $2^k$ points. Thus we have proved that all powers of $2$ work and we are done.
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
coolmath_2018
2807 posts
#22
Y by
We claim that the answer is all $n$ in the form of $2^k$.

We will use induction to show this.
Base Case: $n = 2$ clearly works.
Inductive Step: Assume the system is collapsible for $2^k$ and we wish to prove it for $2^{k+1}$. Clearly we can divide the $2^{k+1}$ tokens into two $2^k$ piles which can be collapsed. Hence, $2^{k+1}$ can be collapsed.

Now we show that only numbers in the form of $2^k$ are collapsable. Assume that we have $n$ tokens where $n \not= 2^k$. Note that if we put $n-1$ tokens at $(0,0)$ and the last token at $(1,0)$ they must collapse at the point $(\tfrac{1}{n}, 0)$. But by repeatedly taking the midpoint, our denominator must be a power of 2, contradicting our assumption. Hence only numbers of the form $2^k$ are collapsable.
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
RedFireTruck
4221 posts
#23
Y by
https://i.postimg.cc/4x3vqpXm/image.png
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
Danielzh
481 posts
#24
Y by
Mogmog8 wrote:
But each token can only move to coordinates of the form $x_1/2^{\alpha_1}+\dots+x_n/2^{\alpha_n}$ so $$\frac{x_1+\dots+x_n}{n}=\frac{x_1}{2^{\alpha_1}}+\dots+\frac{x_n}{2^{\alpha_n}}.$$This is absurd as the p-adic valuation of the left hand side is negative for any $p\mid n,$ $p\neq 2,$ while the p-adic valuation is non-negative for the right hand side. $\square$

Wowwwww very clever thinking :O
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
L13832
252 posts
#25
Y by
For $n=1$ case the sequence is is collapsible, by inductive hypothesis we assume is it is true for $n=2^k$ and now we prove for $n=2^{k+1}$, notice that for $2^{k+1}$ we can divide the sequence of tokens into two parts of $2^k$ size which are collapsible and then collapcing the two points into a single point so the arrangements of $2^{k+1}$ tokens is also collapsible.
Now to prove that no other form other than arrangements of $2^k$ is collapsible. If we place all the tokens on non-negative integer positions on a real number line we will observe that the sum of the $x$-coordinates of all the tokens on a number line remains the same or is an INVARIANT, each $x$-coordinate will collapse to $\displaystyle \frac{(x_1+x_2+...+x_n)}{n}$, this is a contradiction.
because eventually the token can only move to a position with a denominator of a power of $2$, so for an arrangement n should be a power of $2$.
This post has been edited 1 time. Last edited by L13832, Jul 27, 2024, 5:34 AM
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
dolphinday
1318 posts
#26
Y by
If $n$ is a power of $2$ we can keep on putting the tokens in groups of $2$ from which our construction is simple.
If $n$ is not a power of $2$ then put the tokens on the number line in $1$, $2$, $4$, $\dots$, $2^{n-1}$. Note the final spot for which the tokens must end up at is fixed since the sum of each of the tokens on the number line is invariant. So the point on the number line where the tokens must end up is $\frac{2^n-1}{n}$. However the denominator of any token on the number line must be a power of $2$ so the coins can't reach the final position if $n$ is not a power of $2$, done.
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
Topiary
22 posts
#27
Y by
We claim only powers of 2 work. We prove the necessity first. We will induct on the exponent $2^k$ , $\forall k \ge 0$. For $k = 0$ we have $2^0=1$ which is obviously true. We assume the truth for $n = 2^k$. Now split $2^{k+1}$ into two piles of $w^k$, which we assumed to be collapsible. We can pair up one pile on one point and the other half on another point , to which they will collapse to their midpoint.

We now prove that non powers of two won't work. First assume the contrary. Place $n-1$ points on the origin and 1 point at the point $(1,0).$ As the total sum of the coordinates after any individual move is invariant, the final collapsible point will be )$(\frac 1 n,0 )$ However when we repeatedly take the midpoint , we end up wiht a denominator with a power of 2, contradicting our assumption.
\end{proof}
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
EpicBird08
1740 posts
#28
Y by
The answer is $n = 2^k$ where $k$ is a nonnegative integer. To show this works, an induction-type argument can be used. For $k=0,$ do nothing. Otherwise, pair up tokens and perform a move on each pair, and repeat the argument on $k-1$ twice.

To show necessity, suppose that we have a prime $p > 2$ dividing $n.$ We can put the $i$th token at a lattice point $(x_i, y_i)$ such that the sum of the $x_i$ is not divisible by $p.$ Then because the sum of coordinates is invariant, the coordinates of the final point is $\left(\frac{x_1 + \dots + x_n}{n}, \frac{y_1 + \dots + y_n}{n}\right).$ Since $p \mid n$ and doesn't divide the first sum, we need to somehow divide by $p$ when we can only divide by $2.$ This is impossible, hence $n$ must be a power of $2,$ as desired.

Remark: One could just set $y_i = 0$ for all $i$, $x_i = 0$ for $i \ge 2,$ and $x_1 = 1.$ This would also do the trick, but our approach is more general.
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
Saucepan_man02
1300 posts
#29
Y by
Plot the problem in argand plane:

Let each vertex be denoted by $z_k$. Note that: $\sum z_k$ is constant, thus the final point for any collapsible arrangement must be the centroid.
If $n$ is a power of $2$, we clearly see by induction that its collapsible.
If not, then consider $z_1=1, z_2=z_3=\cdots=z_n=0$ which has a centroid of $(\tfrac{1}{n}, 0)$. But, notice that, after every move, we must have every point's real part to be of the form $\tfrac{1}{2^k}$ (or $0$ itself), which leads to contradiction.
Z K Y
The post below has been deleted. Click to close.
This post has been deleted. Click here to see post.
Ilikeminecraft
328 posts
#30
Y by
The answer is all powers of 2. To do 2, it is trivial by induction.
For non powers of 2, line them up on the number line. Then, put $n - 1$ at 0 and one is at $1.$ It is obvious that the sum of all numbers will always be 1. However, all of them must also have finitely many number of 1/0s in the binary expansion. This finishes.
Z K Y
N Quick Reply
G
H
=
a